Volume 14 (2022): Edition 66 (December 2022) Special Edition: Varieties of Context-Sensitivity in a Pluri-Propositionalist Reflexive Semantic Framework
Volume 14 (2022): Edition 65 (November 2022)
Volume 14 (2022): Edition 64 (May 2022)
Volume 13 (2021): Edition 63 (December 2021) Special Edition on Nothing to Come by Correia & Rosenkranz
Volume 13 (2021): Edition 62 (December 2021) Ethics and Aesthetics: Editions at Their Intersection
Volume 13 (2021): Edition 61 (November 2021)
Volume 13 (2021): Edition 60 (May 2021)
Volume 12 (2020): Edition 59 (December 2020)
Volume 12 (2020): Edition 58 (December 2020) SPECIAL ISSUE: ON THE VERY IDEA OF LOGICAL FORM
Volume 12 (2020): Edition 57 (November 2020)
Volume 12 (2020): Edition 56 (May 2020)
Volume 11 (2019): Edition 55 (December 2019) Special Edition: Chalmers on Virtual Reality
Volume 11 (2019): Edition 54 (December 2019) Special Edition: III Blasco Disputatio, Singular terms in fiction. Fictional and “real” names
Volume 11 (2019): Edition 53 (November 2019)
Volume 11 (2019): Edition 52 (May 2019)
Volume 10 (2018): Edition 51 (December 2018) SYMPOSIUM ON JASON STANLEY’S “HOW PROPAGANDA WORKS”
Volume 10 (2018): Edition 50 (December 2018)
Volume 10 (2018): Edition 49 (November 2018)
Volume 10 (2018): Edition 48 (May 2018)
Volume 9 (2017): Edition 47 (December 2017)
Volume 9 (2017): Edition 46 (November 2017)
Volume 9 (2017): Edition 45 (October 2017)
Volume 9 (2017): Edition 44 (May 2017)
Volume 8 (2016): Edition 43 (November 2016)
Volume 8 (2016): Edition 42 (May 2016)
Volume 7 (2015): Edition 41 (November 2015)
Volume 7 (2015): Edition 40 (May 2015)
Volume 6 (2014): Edition 39 (November 2014)
Volume 6 (2014): Edition 38 (May 2014)
Volume 5 (2013): Edition 37 (November 2013)
Volume 5 (2013): Edition 36 (October 2013) Book symposium on François Recanati’s Mental Files
Volume 5 (2013): Edition 35 (May 2013)
Volume 4 (2012): Edition 34 (December 2012)
Volume 4 (2012): Edition 33 (November 2012)
Volume 4 (2012): Edition 32 (May 2012) New Perspectives on Quine’s “Word and Object”
Volume 4 (2011): Edition 31 (November 2011)
Volume 4 (2011): Edition 30 (May 2011) XII Taller d'Investigació en Filosofia
Volume 4 (2010): Edition 29 (November 2010) Petrus Hispanus 2009
Volume 3 (2010): Edition 28 (May 2010)
Volume 3 (2009): Edition 27 (November 2009) Homage to M. S. Lourenço
Volume 3 (2009): Edition 26 (May 2009)
Volume 3 (2008): Edition 25 (November 2008)
Volume 2 (2008): Edition 24 (May 2008)
Volume 2 (2007): Edition 23 (November 2007) Normativity and Rationality
Volume 2 (2007): Edition 22 (May 2007)
Volume 2 (2006): Edition 21 (November 2006)
Volume 1 (2006): Edition 20 (May 2006)
Volume 1 (2005): Edition 19 (November 2005)
Volume 1 (2005): Edition 18 (May 2005)
Volume 1 (2004): Edition 17 (November 2004)
Volume 1 (2004): Edition 16 (May 2004)
Volume 1 (2003): Edition 15 (November 2003)
Volume 1 (2003): Edition 14 (May 2003)
Volume 1 (2002): Edition 13 (November 2002)
Volume 1 (2001): Edition 11 (November 2001)
Volume 1 (2002): Edition 11-12 (May 2002)
Volume 1 (2001): Edition 10 (May 2001)
Volume 1 (2000): Edition 9 (November 2000)
Volume 1 (2000): Edition 8 (May 2000)
Volume 1 (1999): Edition 7 (November 1999)
Volume 1 (1999): Edition 6 (May 1999)
Volume 1 (1998): Edition 5-2 (November 1998) Special Edition: Petrus Hispanus Lectures 1998: o Mental e o Físico, Guest Editors: Joao Branquinho; M. S. Lourenço
Volume 1 (1998): Edition 5-1 (June 1998) Special Edition: Language, Logic and Mind Forum, Guest Editors: Joao Branquinho; M. S. Lourenço
Volume 1 (1998): Edition 4 (May 1998)
Volume 1 (1997): Edition 3 (November 1997)
Volume 1 (1997): Edition 2 (May 1997)
Volume 1 (1996): Edition 1 (December 1996)
Détails du magazine
Format
Magazine
eISSN
2182-2875
Première publication
01 Dec 1996
Période de publication
4 fois par an
Langues
Anglais, Portuguese
Chercher
Volume 14 (2022): Edition 66 (December 2022) Special Edition: Varieties of Context-Sensitivity in a Pluri-Propositionalist Reflexive Semantic Framework
This brief introduction to a special issue of Disputatio succinctly summarizes John Perry’s pluri-propositionalist reflexive framework and notes some potential applications to varieties of context-sensitivity.
The paper shows that contextuals, words such as those discussed by Richard Vallée in his paper, “On local bars and imported beer”, include not only adjectives and nouns but also verbs, prepositions and adverbs. It shows, moreover, contextuals form just one subclass of words whose complements are optional, that is, words analogous to polyadic predicates of predicate logic. Just as different words, when their complements are omitted, give rise to reflexive (to wash), reciprocal (to meet) and indefinite (to eat) construals, so contextuals give rise to an indexical construal. The paper sets out how such optional complements, or polyadic predicates, as it were, can be handled completely with the syntax and semantics of English, without recourse to special pragmatic principles, lexical ambiguity or phonetically null elements. Though not discussed here, the approach nonetheless applies, it seems, to other languages, such as Chinese.
In “Unarticulated Comparison Classes” 2018 [2009], Richard Vallée adopts John Perry’s (2012 [2001]) reflexive-referential theory of meaning and content as well as his concept of unarticulated constituents (Perry 1986) to deal with certain context-sensitive elements of the truth-conditions of statements containing relative gradable predicates. I am sympathetic both with the general framework and with the assumption that unarticulated constituents are involved in the truth-conditions of bare positives such as “Monica is tall.” I do not share, however, Vallée’s main conclusions on the examples he provides as pre-theoretical evidence. This leads me to disagree with some details of his proposal for the semantics and pragmatics of relative gradable adjectives.
A frequent criticism of Richard Vallee’s “pluri-propositionalism” is that it multiplies propositions beyond necessity. I argue that this criticism, recently voiced by Robert Stanton and Arthur Sullivan, is based in misconceptions about propositions are and how they help us classify utterances and the mental states and events that lead to them, relying for the most part on extended discussions of examples.
This is a study of an under-developed topic in philosophy of language, namely first-person plural pronouns (‘we’, ‘us’, etc.) Richard Vallée has made very important progress by identifying crucial desiderata and putting forward an ingenious proposal about ‘we’ which addresses them. We contend that, despite this impressive progress, he makes some missteps, both omissions and errors; furthermore, his proposal appears implausible as a personal-level psychological story. We thus sketch an alternative approach to the semantics of the first-person plural indexical which, though it builds on Vallée’s important work, departs substantially from it.
Both the semantics of fictional discourse and the semantics of indexicality are canonical topics in the philosophy of language, on which there exists well-known significant literature. However, the same cannot be said for the terrain where they overlap. That is, the distinctive issues raised by fictive uses of indexicals and demonstratives have not been extensively studied per se. The aim of the present essay is to shed some light on this terrain, and to advance our understanding of some of these issues. As it happens, accounting for indexicals in fiction requires the use of innovative new tools. In particular, the standard, familiar taxonomy of types / tokens / utterances is not sufficient to account for the complex cognitive significance and truth-conditions, unique to these kinds of case. For instance: it is widely recognized that, with indexicals generally, semantic properties attach to utterances, not to types or to tokens. But in fiction there are no utterances (in the relevant sense). An innovative notion is required, which I call an “indexed token”. This account of indexicals in fiction, based on the notion of an indexed token, is developed within a Perry (2012)-inspired pluri-propositionalist framework. As such, the present essay constitutes an original application of that framework, extending its already impressive reach.
This brief introduction to a special issue of Disputatio succinctly summarizes John Perry’s pluri-propositionalist reflexive framework and notes some potential applications to varieties of context-sensitivity.
The paper shows that contextuals, words such as those discussed by Richard Vallée in his paper, “On local bars and imported beer”, include not only adjectives and nouns but also verbs, prepositions and adverbs. It shows, moreover, contextuals form just one subclass of words whose complements are optional, that is, words analogous to polyadic predicates of predicate logic. Just as different words, when their complements are omitted, give rise to reflexive (to wash), reciprocal (to meet) and indefinite (to eat) construals, so contextuals give rise to an indexical construal. The paper sets out how such optional complements, or polyadic predicates, as it were, can be handled completely with the syntax and semantics of English, without recourse to special pragmatic principles, lexical ambiguity or phonetically null elements. Though not discussed here, the approach nonetheless applies, it seems, to other languages, such as Chinese.
In “Unarticulated Comparison Classes” 2018 [2009], Richard Vallée adopts John Perry’s (2012 [2001]) reflexive-referential theory of meaning and content as well as his concept of unarticulated constituents (Perry 1986) to deal with certain context-sensitive elements of the truth-conditions of statements containing relative gradable predicates. I am sympathetic both with the general framework and with the assumption that unarticulated constituents are involved in the truth-conditions of bare positives such as “Monica is tall.” I do not share, however, Vallée’s main conclusions on the examples he provides as pre-theoretical evidence. This leads me to disagree with some details of his proposal for the semantics and pragmatics of relative gradable adjectives.
A frequent criticism of Richard Vallee’s “pluri-propositionalism” is that it multiplies propositions beyond necessity. I argue that this criticism, recently voiced by Robert Stanton and Arthur Sullivan, is based in misconceptions about propositions are and how they help us classify utterances and the mental states and events that lead to them, relying for the most part on extended discussions of examples.
This is a study of an under-developed topic in philosophy of language, namely first-person plural pronouns (‘we’, ‘us’, etc.) Richard Vallée has made very important progress by identifying crucial desiderata and putting forward an ingenious proposal about ‘we’ which addresses them. We contend that, despite this impressive progress, he makes some missteps, both omissions and errors; furthermore, his proposal appears implausible as a personal-level psychological story. We thus sketch an alternative approach to the semantics of the first-person plural indexical which, though it builds on Vallée’s important work, departs substantially from it.
Both the semantics of fictional discourse and the semantics of indexicality are canonical topics in the philosophy of language, on which there exists well-known significant literature. However, the same cannot be said for the terrain where they overlap. That is, the distinctive issues raised by fictive uses of indexicals and demonstratives have not been extensively studied per se. The aim of the present essay is to shed some light on this terrain, and to advance our understanding of some of these issues. As it happens, accounting for indexicals in fiction requires the use of innovative new tools. In particular, the standard, familiar taxonomy of types / tokens / utterances is not sufficient to account for the complex cognitive significance and truth-conditions, unique to these kinds of case. For instance: it is widely recognized that, with indexicals generally, semantic properties attach to utterances, not to types or to tokens. But in fiction there are no utterances (in the relevant sense). An innovative notion is required, which I call an “indexed token”. This account of indexicals in fiction, based on the notion of an indexed token, is developed within a Perry (2012)-inspired pluri-propositionalist framework. As such, the present essay constitutes an original application of that framework, extending its already impressive reach.