Bad Company: The Corporate Appropriation of Nature, Divinity, and Personhood in U.S. Culture
Published Online: Dec 31, 2019
Page range: 249 - 288
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/bjals-2019-0015
Keywords
© 2019 Richard Hardack, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
In the manner of subliminal advertising, the corporate communications that warn you that someone might be stealing your identity also might be acknowledging that corporations are responsible for the biggest identity theft in history. If corporations are now alive, and have become persons, human beings might already be dead things. In this article, I provide a condensed, necessarily elliptical cultural history of some of the critical concepts pertaining to the impersonal impersonations that constitute corporate personhood. By examining the naturalization, animation, legal authorization and structural deification of the corporate person, I hope to illuminate the ways corporations walk, disembodied, among us.
In a prior publication, I coined the term corpography to connote the limited forms of self-representation—such as advertisements, filings, and corporate histories—that corporations can generate. (1) Advertising, the corporate speech I described as impersonal and depersonalizing, provides a primary means for creating corporate identities, which I define as only a network of representations that reify corporations as coherent, continuous and personalized entities. That discourse inures us to the fantasy that we can relate to corporations as organizations with intrinsic human(oid) characteristics, rather than as legal fabrications or bureaucratic machines. Though it is highly mediated, advertising is the closest thing to an autobiographical utterance a corporation can make. Most external biographical representations of a “corporation” internalize the fantasy that the corporate structure can be incarnated, and narrativize and dramatize the corporate brand as if it were in key registers personable, or impersonable.
I also argued that personhood is a zero sum game, and that the more “personhood” and human rights a corporation attains, the less of those traits and rights people retain. Because it is a purely metaphorical contrivance, the concept of corporate personhood is often represented through images of mechanical, generic, and vampyric forms of existence. In other words, impersonal corporate systems mimic human processes and interactions, or uncannily but defectively imitate and siphon the personal qualities of people—they are entities that steal identities. I focus here not on advertising, but the causes and effects of corporate ontology in the U.S. in cultural and legal terms.
I track the Hobbesian lineage of the corporate form, but also the ways the corporation has filled the cultural space vacated by our abnegation of anthropomorphic notions of god and Nature (i.e., other personified fictions of collective existence that preceded it. I capitalize Nature at points to connote a deified, impersonally personified, and transcendental entity). I briefly touch on the disturbing ways in which pantheist and neo-vitalist theories of Gaea, which personify Nature as a living Being with a soul and agency, can reflect corporate ontologies and help substantiate the legal and deontological frameworks that afford corporations souls and personhood. The pressing question is whether corporations conceptually are persons or nightmarish things impersonating persons.
Commercial entities with strictly delimited rights and liabilities, corporations are created at the largesse of governments or sovereigns; as such, they are ineluctably artificial and contingent. In the well-known U.S. Supreme Court case of
The only interest a corporation has under its charter is commercial—it is created for a strictly mercantile purpose.
(4) No autonomous person exists in the formal corporate domain to generate views, or voice speech, other than agents who make commercial representations regarding the corporation on its behalf. Many other groups and associations can voice any kind of speech—they are not bound by charters, and their privileges were not designed to be balanced by equivalent restrictions. No doubt, such entities face their own problems in voicing the views of a collective, but they are at least in critical ways disconnected from the directives and constraints of the for-profit corporation. Unlike NGOs, partnerships and most other organizations, the large corporation
In many ways, the ever-increasing wealth gap in the United States is actually a personhood gap. The effect of corporate personhood, which operates in tandem with privatization, is to dehumanize people, turning them into things that have no rights—not the right to have access to healthcare, education, or courts rather than arbitration; to retire; to unionize; to speak; and even to vote. Many of those rights have been directly and indirectly transferred to corporations that can lobby and set agendas ranging from taxation to healthcare, education, military spending, election rules, gerrymandering and campaign spending. As codified by the ironically titled
To address the evolving and troubling relationship of the corporation to personhood in U.S. culture, one needs to consider its affiliations with, and divergences from, Nature and the nation-state. I argue that a once deified Nature, which was also putatively animated with some form of a soul, has been superseded directly by the Corporation with a soul, which begins to take on the exceptional, numinous, or inhuman characteristics of the divine—it is a disembodied, collective thing that is animated, ubiquitous and theoretically immortal. The corporation also is engaged in a zero-sum game with Nature, and finally the nation-state. According to Marx, “The devaluation of the human world increases in direct relation with the increase in value of the world of things.” (5) Today, that world is represented by the corporation, the quintessential uncanny Thing whose “human” status, rights and qualities grow as, and only when, those of people are diminished. In tracing how the corporation comes to take on and over the attributes of Nature beginning around the time of the Civil War, one encounters a consistent rhetoric of merger, animation, impersonation, impersonality, artificial life or intelligence, and a transcendence of individual human identity common to both entities.
The relationship between human and corporate personhood and identity implicates our interactions with religion, deified Nature and sacrificial systems of gift exchange. For these reasons, I treat the corporation not primarily as a commercial enterprise—though its legal and economic functions are of course vital to its existence—but as a cultural phantasm, a kind of black hole that draws in more and more cultural phenomena into its orbit. In a variety of contexts, people barter their attributes to corporations—they are not trading liberty for security, but “souls” for identity. As I will argue, the contemporary corporation has come to guarantee certain rights at a price, in much the way the Hobbesian state once did. As the corporation comes to serve as the
In his recent novel
This corporate displacement fulfills an arc Melville first traced in full in
In some ways unprecedented and anomalous in history, the corporation is a private institution that is everywhere, and everywhere precisely the same—and hence not only immortal, but ubiquitous. (13) The franchise is one apotheosis of the corporate form; it is a kind of Platonic archetype that begins as an idea that is then reproduced endlessly to order. An infinitely replicable clone (or work of mechanical reproduction) without an original, the corporation can have the same identity always and everywhere, in some ways because it can have no identity at all, anywhere. In its modern form, it is already a purely digital/virtual/posthuman entity—without a body and yet omnipresent, existing in more than one place at the same time.
These initially maritime joint-stock companies, which settled the new world and for Melville were emblematized by the new global enterprise of whaling, were also intimately involved in all aspects of colonialism and the global slave trade—they were precursors of the modern corporation in many contexts. As Malick Ghachem notes, historians tend to assume the priority of the nation-state over such entities as the corporation as subjects of inquiry; but colonialism was advanced by conflicts between national trading companies as much as it was by disputes among the colonial powers themselves.
(14) (As Joseph Slaughter proposes in slightly different but relevant contexts in discussing Robinson Crusoe, oaths “are also the forms that colonial charter companies used not only to subjugate native peoples but also, in effect, to acquire international personality of their own”).
(15) A form of colonialism is inherent to aspects of the corporate enterprise, and the demands of capital, which seeks constant expansion into nature and other cultures associated with nature. In The danger to Western capitalism comes not from outside, from the Chinese or some other monster beating us at our own game while depriving us of Western liberal individualism, but from the inherent limit of its own process of colonizing ever new (not only geographic, but also cultural, psychic, etc.) domains . . . [until] Capital will no longer have any substantial content outside itself to feed on. . . . [W]hen the circle closes itself, when reflexivity becomes thoroughly universal, the whole system is threatened.
(16)
To explain how the corporation emerges as the successor to or fulfillment of transcendental Nature, I here briefly address pantheistic (primarily) American writers who, perhaps unexpectedly, served as precursors to and harbingers of contemporary corporate culture. The type of transcendentalists most concerned with the collective and impersonal aspects of Nature, pantheists evoked its attributed power, scope, and functions in ways that consistently comport with the same vectors of the “animated” corporation. Many pantheistic depictions of merger with Nature either predict or are co-opted by the corporate age that soon follows. For example, in The animism [that] peopled the outward world with nature spirits was the instinctive protest of man’s heart against the materialism of his conscious thought. . . [When] animism fell into disrepute . . . . it made possible [] scientific exploration . . . . [but] as belief in the supernatural waned . . . . especially in Protestant countries . . . materialism reject[ed] the supernatural, and [gave] a mechanistic explanation of life . . . . [the loss of animism]. . . . empt[ied] nature of her own spiritual life.
(18) [T]he universe as a whole is thrilling in every fibre with Life,—not, indeed, life in the usual restricted sense, but life in a general sense. The distinction, once deemed absolute, between the living and the not-living is converted into a relative distinction; and Life as manifested in the organism is seen to be only a specialized form of the Universal Life. . . . reappearing from moment to moment under myriad Protean forms . . . . [through] this animating principle of the universe.
(19)
Transcendentalists believed that some mysterious, ubiquitous principle or force infused universal Nature and also “animated” all people, representing an impersonal annexation of the personal. Such animation or life could not be restricted to people, or even organic matter; as Melville suggest throughout his novel I live while consciousness is not mine, while to all appearances I am a clod. And may not this same state of being, though but alternate with me, be continually that of many dumb, passive objects we so carelessly regard? Trust me, there are more things alive than those that crawl, or fly, or swim . . . . Think you it is nothing to be a world? . . . what are our tokens of animation? . . . Think you there is no sensation in being a rock?
(21)
For transcendentalists and some political theorists, Nature once served as the universal force that authorized American democracy (as well as manifest destiny). But as the nation-state came to be unified not by Nature—which was imagined to be everywhere the same—but corporate technologies such as the railroad and telegraph, the corporation became the new animated clod. A key question, since transferred to the corporation, is what kind of speech animated Nature could make. Emerson believed that “The Soul which animates nature is not less significantly published in the figure, movement and gesture of animated bodies, than its last vehicle of articulated speech . . . . A statue has no tongue, and needs none.”
(23) As Hawthorne writes in
The law itself once situated corporations as artificial constructions that mimicked nature. Some twentieth-century legal cases, for example, specify that the state animates corporations: “A corporation is a creature of the State. It owes its very being to the State. “Into its nostrils the State must breathe the breath of a fictitious life for otherwise it would be no animated body but individualistic dust [citation omitted].””
(26) Such cases appropriately still treat the corporation as a kind of closely-held Frankenstein’s monster, an animated thing of dust: “While the directors are chosen by the stockholders, they become, when elected and properly organized as a board, the agent of the corporation. It is by such means that animate force is given to an inanimate thing.”
(27) Contrary to most representations of corporations in films and texts, these courts treat the corporation as having no independent life at all, and as a mere contrivance: “Corporations are animated by people; those who control such corporations hire others to perform on the corporation’s behalf.”
(28) This language modifies the descriptions found in text as such as
After Lukács, Michael Rogin proposes that “every cog is human; when power is attributed to emblems, and they do human work, the writer has succumbed to animism.” (29) Transcendental animism—the rhetoric that attributed life, personality and soul to aspects of Nature—was transferred to the corporate form. (30) According to Gregory A. Mark, the idea of a corporation imbued with life did not hold great influence in the United States: “Equally ill-fated were the attempts to animate the corporation, which were not generally taken seriously in America. Nonetheless, commentators recognized the births and deaths of corporations, and accepted that they possessed lives and the powers to will, to act, and to create.” (31) But I would argue that this idea of animation, even if not taken seriously in the general culture until recently, has had profound ramifications and effects and is an indispensible facet of a religious and ontological discourse that pervades U.S. culture. Party as an outgrowth of the legal separation between corporate tortfeasor and individual liability, the corporation has come to possess a life of its own precisely independent of the people who allegedly animate it.
Disturbingly, some posthumanist and neo-vitalist theory, which tries to erase hierarchical distinctions between species and organic and inorganic matter, can play into the notion that the corporation is itself alive, and has personhood, rights, and a soul. For example, under Roberto Esposito’s resuscitation of vitalism—which echoes antebellum pantheism, contends that all life is equal and should be approached impersonally, and is meant to transcend the limitations of the human/humanism—the impersonal corporation could also be considered alive. (32) Here, posthumanism can be used to advance the interest of the posthuman corporation, and the corporation, in precisely structural/impersonal terms, is effectively able to appropriate posthumanist personhood as, we shall see, it did the personhood of African Americans. Similarly, Jane Bennett’s notion of enchanted matter, impersonal affect and heterogeneous/distributive agency could also apply to the same kind of animism that gives corporations the ontological status of persons. (33) To deny the distinction between the living and the non-living can play directly into the absent hands of the corporation. Such theorists sometimes confuse the impersonal, which they tether to a rights discourse, with the egalitarian; the excesses that can mar personal discourses do not warrant their abandonment, but regulation.
In the United States, the history of the corporation also tracks the shift from romanticism to naturalism and back to neo-romanticism, all of which, perhaps surprisingly, maintain many of the same premises regarding the aggregate forces of Nature/the corporation, and primarily shift only their reaction to those premises. Under naturalism, nature represents an impersonal automaton, an emblem of brute/blind force. Yet as Walter Benn Michaels suggests—through the “discrepancy between the behavior of individuals and that of the aggregate”—Nature ultimately can turn everything into (and problematize the very notion of) a person: “dreaming of the “monstrous,” [Frank Norris’] Presley [in
Beginning with Hobbes, the teleology of the corporate form would take it from being a surrogate for a deified Nature and “centralizing” nation-state to being their successor or near-successor. Melissa Aronczyk observes that corporate advertisers and branding agencies now legitimate and maintain the nation-state as one of our primary cultural reference points. (35) However, the corporation has in some ways overtaken the nation-state as the most significant producer of laws and cultural signifiers. (Jorg Kustermans argues that the nation-state also effectively utilizes its legal status to claim personhood, in a form of republican identity-construction comparable to the construction of individual personhood, but I would argue that it is critical to differentiate formulations of individual personhood from those of aggregate personhood). (36) In the twenty first century, nation-states often fragment or become engaged in civil, sectarian, religious and postcolonial wars—corporations, by contrast, tend to consolidate and expand. As John Meyer and Patricia Bromley remark in addressing the recent rise of organizations generally world-wide, “An overarching explanation is that the dramatic limitations of the nation-state system, especially two horrific world wars, undermined government-based control, [thereby] creating supports for alternative forms of a more global social order.” (37)
In the next section, I focus briefly on Richard Powers’ novel
As David Foster Wallace intimates throughout
Maliszewski cites Powers’ own impression that “the literary approach” to business, which relies on humanist principles and characters to dramatize corporate systems, has become inadequate, and led him to pursue an articulation of the impersonal. (42) In other words, the old constraints of fiction prevent it from being able to apprehend the new contrivances of corporate fiction. Powers explicitly proposes that “the corporate protagonist’s cycle of boom and bust [is] substituting for a narrative’s rise and fall.” (43) Powers’ narrator then tells us, “with the right corporate structure, decisions practically handled themselves”: that is, human agency, along with many of the very structures of narrative and biography and the human life cycle, recede or even disappear into impersonal discourse, and the recycling and inhuman cadences of corporate life cycles. (44) Such fictions narrativize not just an invisible hand, but the development of an entire corpus that is non-existent; in other words, we are left with decisions without decision-makers, shadows without casters, impersonators without persons.
Beginning with their Hobbesian chartered inceptions, corporations have always been artificial entities imbued with personhood, or souls. The deafening, largely unregulated speech they make in most contemporary societies is perversely proportionate to the absence of an identifiable speaker (behind the spokesperson)—ultimately, theirs is speech without an individual orator or source, but it generates a discourse that permeates everything. As Maliszewski notes, in
For Powers, well before the
But in the ontological and practical economic aspects of the zero sum game of personhood, corporate enfranchisement was gained at the expense of the disenfranchised. African-American slaves were freed and became legal persons under the aegis of due process, but corporations, the greater Elvis, effectively appropriated those rights. Corporations asserted they too had the rights of natural persons under the Fourteenth Amendment (petitions that have since grown into claims of aggregations of super rights, which allow corporations, in terms of reach and effect, to broadcast what are in effect millions of voices in their own names). Instead of being fractions of people, corporations became composites of all people. But African Americans had to invoke the rights of corporate persons to enforce their civil rights; they were able to challenge segregation under
“We have to take the power back from the Parliament and put it where it belongs.”
“With the East India Company?” I proposed.
“That is exactly right: with the East India Company, and the chartered companies, and those men of wealth and ingenuity who wield the power in our economy. To them must go the spoils of the earth, not members of parliament.”
The history of the corporation is closely connected to the history of the modern state, the abstract collective that provides an aggregate identity to those who belong to it or live under its field of influence. Hobbes could guarantee the continuity of the state by making it an impersonal entity that traversed the lifespans and limitations of individual rulers; the state was represented by particular sovereigns or men, but they were in a critical sense mere placeholders. Similarly, the corporation becomes an impersonal structure, precisely divorced from its owners or employees, who are not only temporary, but, in relative terms, fungible. Like the nation-state, the corporation is an impersonality we are in service to, but one that ultimately displaces and supplants its subjects; it is as if we have ended up as hosts to the impersonality, which has become more virulent, resistant, and embedded over time.
It is important to consider the relationship of the corporation, the current body of power in society, to its antecedent forms, particularly the bodies of Nature and the king. The corporate body retains but transforms the mystical and inhuman properties associated with the king’s body; as with a sovereign body, it represents a conjunction of an extra-human body and an exceptional or non-human personality (though many now would allege that the king and corporation also are equally persons). Aggregate and symbolic bodies of power typically bear contradictory or mystical attributes. In many cultures, for example, “It was not proper to refer to [the king’s] body or to imply that he had an ordinary human body at all. A special word was used instead, signifying the kingly personality.” (52) Ironically, whereas “the crucial thing about the king is his uniqueness,” the crucial thing about the modern corporation is its ubiquity and uniformity—it champions apparent uniqueness through its brute universality. (53) In the corporate state, the function of this collectivized body is still to represent power—but in the corporation it is stripped of the specific overlay of human personality (except as manifested in the ventriloquism of advertising).
Yet as Žižek might argue, a corporate figurehead typically must be created through a process of fetishization and reification, or
the “false ‘personalization’ (‘psychologization’) of what are in fact objective social processes. It was in the 1930s that the first generation of Frankfurt School theoreticians drew attention to how—at the very moment when global market relations started to exert their full domination, making the individual producer’s success or failure dependent on market cycles totally out of his control—the notion of a charismatic ‘business genius’ reasserted itself in ‘spontaneous capitalist ideology,’ attributing the success or failure of a businessman to some mysterious
Hobbes’ work remains critical for understanding the artificial person of the corporation and its relation to bodies—bodies of power, science fiction bodies, and dematerialized bodies. In political as well as sociological contexts, the corporation has become a less accountable version of the absolute sovereign, as well as the embodiment of actorhood and agency, Hobbes imagined that the state had to be. Beyond a king, the corporation is both hyper-embodied and disembodied. That erstwhile disembodiment of course does not diminish the materiality of the corporate form, even as a legal fiction, or its effects; that putative “immateriality” is a construct that serves to bolster and shield corporate power. (55) For Michaels, the possibility of a corporate person/personality without a body represents a form of idealism or fantasy—one, I would add, that further removes the corporation from the world of lived reality to the world of the sublime or numinous horror. (56) Michaels observes that “Whereas in a partnership, the death of a partner dissolves the partnership, in [the view of Josiah] Royce [the philosopher of American corporate life], no physical event can jeopardize the life of the corporate entity—its soul is immortal.” (57) The corporation begins as a figurative, culturally-constructed body, but ends as a disembodied everlasting soul, and that trajectory remains related to U.S. conceptions of the materiality of collective Nature. The corporation and Nature are both fictions that we embody and reify, and to which we give a shape, characteristics, and even voice. (This premise also helps explain the narratives of some reflexive mysteries; because we must ventriloquize the dumb corporation and project its essence—the mysterious voice we cannot identify—the agents/actors of crimes we cannot trace or account for often turn out to be not just corporate malefactors, but us all along. The detective/analyst often seeks himself, and in the context of social “mysteries,” corporations often serve as a screen for enacting our repressed social unconscious. In Lacanian terms, when we hear the corporation speak, it is our voice we are hearing, or getting back, distorted).
The corporation fulfills one particularly American cultural fantasy regarding the transcendence of materiality. The goal of Emerson’s transcendentalism is to
The modern form of the corporate enterprise also performs many of the precepts of poststructural semiotics—for example, it advances a deliberate disconnection of act/speech from source/intention. In most contexts, we have corporate signifieds, and, both legally and ontologically, no signifiers of a different sort—no one responsible for them legally or culturally. In symbolic and practical ways, as DeLillo intimates throughout
But I also would contend that corporations are not primarily communicating about products or even themselves: they are communicating, performing and proliferating an epistemology and ontology, and in this sense also serve as our last Big Others, systems without centers, disquisitions without speakers, constellations of effects and processes without causes or affects.
As we can see in many Hollywood films, some forms of such corporate ventriloquism are connected to anxieties regarding possession and dispossession: for example, the dead that colonize life, and speak through and inhabit us. The undead and the many forms of artificial or altered beings that look as if they were alive, but only imitate life, often have some affinity with the corporate person. What Hobbes describes as the artificial person of the corporation in part evolves into a form of artificial intelligence, embodied in the various science fiction and horror film impersonations of the human form. Aside from the fact that some corporations rely heavily on technologies that simulate and even replace life, and what we might term a myriad of reality simulators—from games to movies and Japanese sex robots—impersonated forms of reality are typically produced by, and are unnatural allies of, corporations because they all involve imitations of life. (Benjamin Sovacool argues that the corporation itself has emerged as an unrecognized form of instrumentally successful, but socially failing, technology). (61) The novelist Philip K. Dick became fascinated by Alan Turing’s experiments to evaluate whether we can verify what it means to be human: specifically, whether machines can think, or convince us they are thinking, or, when not present, that they are actual human beings. (62) Turing’s postulate was that something is human if it can convince another human it is. That assertion raises the question, how does the person doing the comparison know it is itself human? The corporate person is a quintessential generator and example of artificial intelligence. Dick’s litmus test for a human being, however, was not whether it could convince a person it was human, but whether it possessed empathy, (63) a test a corporate person would fail, because it is programmed by law to care about profits above anything else. People almost have universally feared that some supernatural force or version of the devil could impersonate the human form. Our concern that we can no longer isolate or differentiate human from inhuman cogitation has of course increased with our reliance on virtual realities and internet communication, a world run by computers. Our fear now is not only that a corporation can impersonate the human form, but that the human form has become obsolete, and now impersonates the corporate form.
The characteristically artificial personhood of the corporation should now be situated in the context of the artificial world of simulations and computers, but also of the collective body of the state—itself a kind of foundational science fiction motif. As Sharon Cameron summarizes the Hobbesian lineage of personhood,
The word
The legal creation of personhood made it possible to redefine human identity within the confines of the nation-state; ultimately, we could take personhood away by treating someone as a thing, or, conversely create personhood by treating a thing as if it had personal attributes and rights. In other words, if we begin with a definition of personhood that situates the concept as not simply constructed, but pointedly artificial, it is almost inevitable that our other institutions, such as corporations, will be defined under similar coordinates. Hobbes begins the subordination of personality to impersonality in his conception of the corporate form. As Cameron continues,
For Hobbes, the definition of a person (or agent) is what we agree to treat as a person; a being is determined human not by philosophical definitions or by man, but by law. To be a person or agent, according to Hobbes, it is not sufficient to consider yourself a person; you must also be considered as possessing agency. In distinction,
Hobbes is one of the first modern theorists of agency and agency law—his work addresses who can represent whom and what, on whose behalf, and with what responsibility and liability. As Quentin Skinner observes, Hobbes “informs us in Chapter XVI of for an action genuinely to be attributed to a collectivity—or to an abstraction or even a thing—provided that one particular condition is met. The agent to whom the action is attributed must be represented by another agent who can validly claim to be ‘personating’ the first by way of acting on their behalf.
(67) PERSON, is he, whose words or actions are considered, either as his own, or as representing the words or actions of another man, or of any other thing to whom they are attributed, whether Truly or by Fiction. When they are considered as his own, then is he called a Natural Person and when they are considered as representing the words and actions of another, then is he a Feigned or Artificial person.
(68)
Addressing how Hobbes classifies fictions of personhood (which become salient for the creation of corporations), Skinner observes that
Hobbes proposes no particular term to isolate this category, but it may be helpful to designate them purely artificial persons to distinguish them from those who voluntarily take on this status by authorizing others to represent them. . . . Hobbes [indicates] that two sub-classes need to be considered: those whose words and actions can be ‘truly’ attributed to them, and those who can only have words and actions attributed to them ‘by Fiction.’ Nothing further is said in If I play the part of Agamemnon on the stage, the actions I perform . . . will not ‘truly’ be taken to be Agamemnon’s actions, however, but only ‘by fiction’ and a willing suspension of disbelief. This will especially be the case if I follow the convention of pointing out that I am merely engaged in a performance.
(69)
Skinner identifies the initial bases for artificial agency or personhood, which also provide a foundation for the development of artificial rights:
Hobbes regards some human beings as purely artificial in this sense. But he is more interested in the fact that various inanimate objects and even figments of the imagination can be classified in a similar way. . . . Since these are ‘things Inanimate’ they ‘cannot be Authors, nor therefore give Authority to their Actors.’ Nevertheless, they can perfectly well be personated or represented ‘by a Rector, Master, or Overseer’ who can be commissioned and thereby given authority to act on their behalf. Among imaginary objects he singles out the gods of the heathen. Such idols obviously cannot be authors, ‘for an Idol is nothing.’” Nevertheless, in ancient times such deities were frequently recognized as having the ability not merely to own possessions but to exercise rights. As in the case of the hospital and the bridge, these capacities stemmed from the fact that authorized persons (in this case officiating priests) were assigned a legal right to act in their name.
(70)
Hobbes, however, believed the representative/sovereign and those who authorized him were accountable for their actions, and that those actions could be directly ascribed to their agents; he authorized the exercise of power, not its absolution. But the power concentrated in the body of the sovereign has become concentrated in the body of the corporation—an artificial body even more removed from people. Wanting the state to restrain and regulate individual violence and economic crime, Hobbes believed an impersonal system could regulate the behavior of personal players. But the impersonal corporation increasingly took over, and it is in critical ways unregulated and unchecked in power; this denouement reflects a systemic corruption of the principles that hypothetically justified the legitimate but limited function of corporations. In this Hobbesian lineage, the sovereign state charters/creates/empowers the Mephistophelean corporation that will inevitably try to commit state parricide.
In
In Hobbes’ writing, we can see that the creation of the modern state was in many ways coterminous with the creation of the proto-corporate enterprise. In In a body politic, for the well ordering of foreign traffic, the most commodious representative is an assembly of all the members; that is to say, such a one as every one that adventures his money may be present at all the deliberations and resolutions of the body, if they will themselves. For proof whereof we are to consider the end for which men that are merchants, and may buy and sell, export and import their merchandise, according to their own discretions, do nevertheless bind themselves up in one corporation. It is true, there be few merchants that with the merchandise they buy at home can freight a ship to export it; or with that they buy abroad, to bring it home; and have therefore need to join together in one society, where every man may either participate of the gain, according to the proportion of his adventure, or take his own, and sell what he transports, or imports, at such prices as he thinks fit. But this is no body politic, there being no common representative to oblige them to any other law than that which is common to all other subjects.
(74)
The “body politic”—and the notion that society is an organic community, a social body—is supplemented and deformed by the corporation, another fictitious aggregate body, representing an entity that is precisely immaterial. If, in traditional, conservative social theory, “the presupposed organic unity of Society is perturbed by the intrusion of a foreign body,” the unity of our society is now in many ways predicated on the presence of a
As the idea has played out in U.S. culture, to incorporate is not to join a common society, but to transcend individuality—in a society putatively obsessed with individuality—in some larger natural or artificial body. To incorporate is in some ways to merge one’s individual body into a collective body, to renounce human limitations, and, in the centuries after Hobbes, the common in favor of the private shareholder. But the paradox is that many corporations systematically invert the characteristics of the public and the private, from concepts of privacy to those of public benefit and welfare. In If there is a philosophical system which teaches that all things material and immaterial . . . are to be considered only as the several parts of an immense Being, who alone remains eternal amidst the continual change and ceaseless transformation of all that constitutes him . . . such a system, though it destroy the individuality of man, or rather because it destroys that individuality, will have secret charms for men living in democracies. . . . It naturally attracts and fixes their imagination.
(78)
After the Civil War, virtually all transcendental rhetoric of Union in Nature became deflected to rhetorics of incorporation (which in figurative terms also often entailed individual dismemberment). The sometimes seemingly abstract contest between the individual and the corporate mass is evident in more concrete terms, for example, in the jury instructions of an 1886 Mississippi Supreme Court case:
This poor negro has the same right to have his matters adjudicated as the defendant, but things have come to such a pass in this country that a railroad company is very much injured if an humble man dares to bring them into the courts. If he dares to appeal to the juries of the country, it is high treason. I say you must consider who the parties are, and who is more likely to overawe witnesses, -a corporation of this sort, or a private individual. I put it to your own knowledge of human nature, whether it is not true that immense corporations, controlling immense armies of operatives, are not more likely to overawe witnesses . . . .
(81)
Accumulation and aggregation are usually zero-sum games; the more money, power, sheer mass and ontological privilege corporations have, the less is left to individuals. As many science fiction films suggest, we increasingly feel as if we are being fed into a giant machine. Transcendentalists had fantasized that Nature was a bulwark against and alternative to the mechanistic corporation and the emerging corporate society, but the language used to evoke both entities revealed a discursive and ontological commonality. Emerson had wanted men to merge into Nature and not society. In his overtly Hobbesian mode, Emerson notably warned in “Self-Reliance” that “Society is a joint-stock company, in which the members agree, for the better securing of his bread to each shareholder, to surrender the liberty and culture of the eater. The virtue in most request [sic] is conformity. Self-reliance is its aversion.” (88) But by self-reliance, Emerson always meant god-reliance—reliance on an archetypal self that transcended individuality and became representative. Emerson believed only in an “aboriginal self,” a self displaced by the archetypal and the Over-Soul. (89) Ironically, in trying to avoid merging with the corporate society/state, Emerson proposed merging with a Nature even more corporate, immense, impersonal and dispossessing. (90)
In
I don’t have space to document the assertion at length, but American pantheists emblematically seek to transcend the boundaries of individual male identity, and merge with other men into collective Nature; and they lose individual agency and will, believing that their actions become archetypal and even involuntary in Nature. These processes actually comport with the premises of, and culminate in, the post-industrial corporation. The language of pantheism is one of merger into Nature—a rosy melting of all into one, or the one into the divine All. (96) That rhetoric of merger in Nature has become that of corporate merger and incorporation. Ironically, though it remains the symbol of capitalism, the corporation from Hobbes onward is fiercely anti-individualistic in its organization, operation, premises and effects. If Hobbes conceived of the sovereign as a “God on earth,” its initial extension and final successor, the corporation, this indescribable mass, comes to attain not only its own soul, but the power to create and steal souls, making it a kind corporate Over-Soul. (97)
Instead of merging with Nature, a prospect writers such as Emerson and Whitman extolled, people began merging into corporations: Michaels asserts, for example, that for Cyclone Davis, “the individual is merged in the money machine of which he is an integral part.”
(98) The corporation represents a mechanical version of a transcendental Nature that is revealed to have been mechanical all along. It is not merely a rhetorical echo that the process of commercial aggregation is called a corporate merger, another manifestation of the ways corporations imitate and usurp psychological and ontological characteristics of people. The sociologists John Meyer and R. L. Jepperson contend that in earlier
religious polities, and in the secularized formations that eventually built upon them, spiritual charisma could be distributed across three main locations: (a) in a central institutional complex (a monarchy, a high Church, a state); (b) in the community as an organic body (that is, in a sacralized matrix of relations [e.g., a system of corporate orders]); or (c) in spiritualized subunits (namely, individuals empowered as souls carrying responsibility for responsible action, whether individually or associationally).
(99)
As Melville established in
[a] ‘monoculture.’” (105) As George Steiner observes, in translatable contexts, “The thought of a more or less monoglot world is no longer inconceivable.” (106) According to David Harvey, we should see post-war Fordism “less as a mere system of mass production and more as a total way of life,” and one might modify that term as totalizing. (107) At the level that affects the vast majority of Americans on a daily basis, the culture of corporations is a monomaniacally monotonous infestation—it requires not just mass production and consumption, but mass culture, a kind of monopolistic consolidation of wealth, power, networks of distribution, and speech under the façade of diversity. It is not accidental, but a necessary consequence of corporate unification, universality and Hobbesian sovereignty that we increasingly are exposed, at any meaningful level and in almost the entire developed world, primarily to corporate media and art: the monopoly corporations most tend to effectuate is not primarily economic, but psychological, cultural, sociological, and ontological.
Hobbes imagined the very purpose of the corporation was to corner markets—and in some sense to consolidate those who give it agency into its aggregate being:
The end of their incorporating is to make their gain the greater; which is done two ways: by sole buying, and sole selling, both at home and abroad. So that to grant to a company of merchants to be a corporation, or body politic, is to grant them a double monopoly, whereof one is to be sole buyers; another to be sole sellers. For when there is a company incorporate for any particular foreign country, they only export the commodities vendible in that country; which is sole buying at home, and sole selling abroad. For at home there is but one buyer, and abroad but one that selleth; both which is gainful to the merchant, because thereby they buy at home at lower, and sell abroad at higher, rates: and abroad there is but one buyer of foreign merchandise, and but one that sells them at home, both which again are gainful to the adventurers.
(108)
What kind of person or personhood exists beneath the corporate veil, the legal shroud that obscures the non-existent Oz? For Hobbes, personhood itself is a mask or performance, and we all present ourselves to the world through personae that constitute personhood:
The word person is Latin, instead whereof the Greeks have prosopon, which signifies the face, as persona in Latin signifies the disguise, or outward appearance of a man, counterfeited on the stage; and sometimes more particularly that part of it which disguises the face, as a mask or vizard: and from the stage hath been translated to any representer of speech and action, as well in tribunals as theatres.
Advocating that we pursue a purely representative, aggregated existence (which would ultimately entail an ascension to impersonal genius), Emerson is interested only in the “moments in the history of heaven when the human race was not counted as individuals, but was only the Influ enced, was God in distribution.” (111) God or the corporation gathers these distributed individuals or fragments into a collective mass existence that transcends locality and particularity. Contrary to popular misconceptions of his notion of self-reliance, Emerson rarely considers anyone or anything in individual terms: as he admonishes with unusual precision, “We fancy men are individuals; so are pumpkins.” (112) Throughout his essays and journals, Emerson averred that God is “no respecter of persons,” and that in our truest relations with the divine and ourselves “there is no personeity in it.” (113) For Emerson, the representative man must “disindividualize himself” and align with “the universal mind.” (114) “In “Fate,” Emerson promises and warns that the Law of Nature “dissolves persons.” (115) Again, the corporation now implements this law. Though his Laws of Nature promise a compensatory unity, Emerson periodically concedes the cost: “These forces are in an ascending series, but seem to leave no room for the individual.” (116) In Emerson’s highly corporate Nature, the uniformity and universality of natural law is paramount, and truth is effectively equivalent to mass; for Emerson, “the individual is always wrong.” (117)
Emerson believed Nature spoke through him in ways that turned him into a kind of corporate spokesperson for larger forces: “Through me, God acts; through me, speaks.” (118) Such sentiments recur throughout Emerson, though they are voiced most directly in his writings of experience. Emerson finally fears that “nothing is of us or our works—that all is of god. Nature will not spare us the smallest leaf of laurel. All writing comes by the grace of God.” (119) A version of Tocqueville’s immense divine being, the corporation again seems to displace the function of Nature; it bears the transcendental, collective identity that speaks through us. But even more ominously, the apparent opposition between Nature and corporation disappears, a process symbolically concluded as corporations begin to control most forms of media speech, patent genes and seeds, and effectively modify and create life. (120)
In Hobbes’ proto-corporate conception, to be a person is already a corporate personification. Hobbes then distinguishes between personally-validated acts and authorized acts, which are essentially impersonal or impersonations:
Of persons artificial, some have their words and actions owned by those whom they represent. And then the person is the actor, and he that owns his words and actions is the author, in which case the actor acts by authority. For that which in speaking of goods and possessions is called an owner . . . speaking of actions, is called author. And . . . by authority is always understood a right of doing any act; and done by authority, done by commission or license from him whose right it is. From hence it follows that when the actor makes a covenant by authority, he binds thereby the author no less than if he had made it himself; and no less subjects him to all the consequences of the same. . . .
(121) There are few things that are incapable of being represented by fiction. Inanimate things, as a church, a hospital, a bridge, may be personated by a rector, master, or overseer. But things inanimate cannot be authors, nor therefore give authority to their actors: yet the actors may have authority to procure their maintenance, given them by those that are owners or governors of those things. And therefore such things cannot be personated before there be some state of civil government.
(122)
Hobbes’ disquisitions are concerned with the forms of safety and security that depend on the guarantees of the state, but also set the boundaries of what constitutes a person with rights and identity:
Likewise children, fools, and madmen that have no use of reason may be personated by guardians, or curators, but can be no authors during that time of any action done by them, longer than (when they shall recover the use of reason) they shall judge the same reasonable. Yet during the folly he that hath right of governing them may give authority to the guardian. But this again has no place but in a state civil, because before such estate there is no dominion of persons.
(124) A multitude of men are made one person when they are by one man, or one person, represented; so that it be done with the consent of every one of that multitude in particular. For it is the unity of the representer, not the unity of the represented, that makes the person one. And it is the representer that bears the person, and but one person: and unity cannot otherwise be understood in multitude. And because the multitude naturally is not one, but many, they cannot be understood for one, but in any authors, of everything their representative say or do in their name; every man giving their common representer authority from himself in particular, and owning all the actions the representer does, in case they give him authority without stint: otherwise, when they limit him in what and how far he shall represent them, none of them owns more than they gave him commission to act.
(125)
Today, the corporation acts as this Hobbesian unity—it is ubiquitous, inescapable and perhaps the greatest force of consolidation in history. According to Peter d’Errico, the role of the judiciary has been to turn the fiction of the corporate person from a legal abstraction into a “real” person that now exists independently of the state (and effectively exists sui generously), that could then negotiate with the state as an independent actor with all the rights of a person. (126) Such developments, and the aforementioned separation of capital from management, are scenarios Hobbes could not quite anticipate, and help vitiate the assurance of corporate accountability.
To sum up, Hobbes indicates that agents can impersonate anything; that all things can be personified; and by implication, that not only persons, but gods can be impersonated: as Hobbes avers, “Men Women, a Bird, A Crocodile, a Calf, a Dog, a Snake, an Onion, a Leeke [brooke], Deified.” (127) The final species to add to that list is the corporation, or the corporate person—a deity made in man’s worst image.
“In not having a face, or even body, the [corporate] Project garnered for itself enormous and far-reaching capabilities, while at the same time reducing its accountability and vulnerability—to almost zero. . . . There was no building, no Project Headquarters . . . . The Project was supra-governmental, supra-national, supra-everything—and infra too;
In the corporation, collective, impersonal biography overtakes the individual life narrative. Writers such as Powers and McCarthy narrativize what Robbie Floyd-Davis documents as the corporate cooption of narrative and biographical discourses, evident, for example, in the ways corporations hire academics—especially anthropologists, sociologists, and story-tellers—to help them directly and indirectly to tell stories about them.
(129) In terms of production—films, media and publishing—but also their “self”-representation, corporations are the dominant aesthetic and ontological influence in our culture. The rise of the corporation coincides with the cultural shift from individual (or self, agent, author, authority, etc.) to system. Powers observes that Tom LeClair’s definition of the systems novel assumes that “the individual human cannot be adequately understood as an autonomous, self-expressing, self-reflecting entity, but must be seen as a node of an immensely complex
Legally created as a screen for individuals—to shield them from liability—the corporation has come to serve as a screen for the systemic displacement of the individual. That is, the corporation is socially and ontologically devised to perform tasks that individuals cannot pragmatically and economically, but also legally and ethically, pursue. It is an impersonal and pre-programmed system designed to coordinate behavior that could harm the common good. No single person is generally responsible for, or even perpetrating, the acts of a corporation, and usually no one can be held responsible; individuality is in fact systematically purged and evacuated from the system.
As intimated, writers have been positing for centuries that corporations emblematically have no souls, yet are still attributed with wills. Jameson details how the corporate form can thwart historical-materialist notions of agency and teleology: Marxists had trouble conceiving of
Some nonindividual, meaningful, collective yet impersonal agency {the mode of production] . . . still somehow a “subject,” like the individual consciousness, yet now immortal, impersonal in another way, collective beyond the dreams of populism . . . . the trust, the monopoly, the “soulfull” corporation, with its new corporate law.
(133)
In the 1920s, John Dewey noted that under “fiction theory,” which construes corporate personality as a contrivance rather than actual, the corporation has no soul and therefore cannot be “guilty of delict,” meaning liable, or perhaps culpable, for causing injury.
(136) In 2000, Thomas Frank alleged that “no one has seriously charged a corporation with “soullessness” for many years,” but that pronouncement is oddly tone-deaf culturally, both retroactively and proactively.
(137) The king’s “personality” once served as kind of carapace for the corporate body; now we are left with corporate personality, which is no human personality at all, a state of things that has ramifications across our entire culture. In
In the private sector that now barely can be distinguished from the public, Clay Timon, chairman of Landor Associates, the influential branding firm, insists that corporations, as brands, do have souls, and that those souls enable them to generate emotional connections with consumers. (140) If society can suppose that a thing can be infused with life, it is inevitable that that thing will claim a soul. David Allen documents the historical processes through which corporations have attempted (what I would characterize as) the colonization of personhood: “Having secured legal standing as people under the Constitution by the mid 1800s, corporations began looking for other ways to establish their humanness. In the 1900s, corporations began focusing on social welfare issues and public relations to convince people they had a soul.” (141) The corporation is the quintessential inhuman thing allegedly imbued with a soul or human personality: a specter haunting the world that was never alive, whose agentless teleology is to convince us it is us.
Trustees of Dartmouth Coll. v. Woodward, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 518, 636 (1819).
Herbert Hovenkamp,
Non-profit corporations—for example, most universities—are distinct entities, but even they increasingly are infiltrated by the structures, expectations, and behaviors of for-profit corporations. Even most B corporations, the relatively miniscule number of corporations that are dedicated to social causes such as renewable energy, are still defined and constrained by the corporate form; while some of these businesses behave much more responsibly than the average corporation, they still use their social agendas to promote their businesses, and to brand themselves as putatively anti-corporate, while still taking advantage of the corporate form.
K
Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, Inc., 573 U.S. 682 (2014).
R corporations, both sole and aggregate, is their perpetuity, assured by laws of intestate succession. Maine’s maxim that ‘corporations never die’ puts the emphasis on the preservation and devolution of the collectively held universitas juris, the bundle of rights and duties . . . . Fortes writes . . . The point here is that it is not their co-existence as ‘a plurality of persons collected in one body’ that makes a group corporate, but their ‘plurality in succession,’ their perpetuity in time. Summing up these ideas [in
Corporate personhood also destabilizes what Michael Vicaro terms the
dualistic model of the self [that] is a central feature of philosophical liberalism. On one side of the liberal split-subject is the “private self,” comprised of the unique particularities of one’s corporeal and relational experiences; this private self is presumed to be inviolable and inaccessible to outside others but for the willfully consented to (and always imperfect) exchange of signs. On the other side stands the “public self,” achieved by virtue of a process of “citizenly abstraction,” by which the individual transcends private interests and becomes a representative of a rational community of impartial “stranger relations.” The liberal individual thus maintains a natural, primary, and extra-discursive personhood, endowed with inalienable rights, and able through rational consent to take on temporarily on any number of subject-positions and citizenly roles. The liberal citizen, for example, must abstract himself or herself from private interests and concerns to occupy the position of a soldier or a public official, but this is an identity position maintained through consent that can be revoked, thus returning one to a neutral and inalienable core self.
N
H
D
D
According to the New Zealand novelist Ian Wedde, whose 1986 novel No doubt about it, Captain Wilkes is Captain Ahab. . . . And Wilkes had a brilliant megalomania before which the democratic American ethos quailed. . . . But it gets even weirder. Wilkes was Ahab, and his backer was one of the spiritual fathers of American corporate vision protected by naval power. . . . behind the rapid debouchement of [Wilkes’] Great [Exploring] Expedition there lurks a shadowy . . . Rhode Island millionaire of the 1840s . . . and crank, one Jeremiah N. Reynolds [believer in the hollow earth, author of the original “Mocha Dick: Or the White Whale of the Pacific,” and forbear of the R.J. Reynolds Tobacco dynasty] . . . . [H]e must have had some vision of corporate structures bestriding the Pacific. . . Reynolds wanted to get
The “residence” and “citizenship” of a corporation matters of course in the context of jurisdiction and local regulation. In what typically involved a race to the bottom, U.S. corporations began to incorporate in states, primarily Delaware, that offered not only the most comprehensive legal system, but the most permissive rules for incorporation and corporate liability and taxation. While some states, such as California, enacted legislation related to incorporation that would protect shareholders, most corporations could simply shop for better provisions elsewhere. But the state of incorporation is largely a fiction of locality and specificity, and another provision that allows for the kind of conceptual disconnection endemic to the corporate form; it has little bearing on where a corporation actually conducts its business or its ontological status as stateless. Many corporations that incorporate in Delaware, for example, simply maintain the equivalent of a post box there, without any attendant human presence.
Malick Ghachem, The Forever Company: How to Narrate the Story of an Eighteenth-Century Legal Person (The Case of the Campaignie des Indes), Address Before the Legal Bodies Conference, Leiden University Centre for Arts in Society (May 17, 2014). Corporate names often reflect the conceptual and linguistic processes of capitalist mergers, which in perverse ways appear to imitate what capitalists often fantasize represents the Darwinian violence of nature. Chemical Bank, for example, takes over or cannibalizes Chase Bank, but retains the “conquered” name or vanquished logo as its company brand. In this variation of what Richard Slotkin terms regeneration through violence, the victorious corporation incorporates to itself through forms of sublimated and sometimes direct aggression.
Joseph R. Slaughter,
S
Ghachem,
E
J
H
J
VI, R
IV, N
A
Cloverfields Improv. Assoc. v. Seabreeze Props., Inc., 32 Md. App. 421, 425 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1976).
Lamb v. Lehmann, 143 N.E. 276, 278 (Ohio 1924).
Chemtall, Inc. v. Citi-Chem, Inc., 992 F. Supp. 1390, 1403 (S.D. Ga. 1998).
M
Though I don’t have space to develop the claim here, I argue that
As if addressing
Gregory A. Mark,
W
M
John W. Meyer & Patricia Bromley,
J
Paul Maliszewski,
D
P
Maliszewski,
P
Maliszewski,
Robert Mankoff,
P
Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v. United States, 379 U.S. 241 (1964).
Responding to a challenge to the Civil Rights Act in 1964, for example, the Court stated that “Section 201 (a) of Title II commands that all persons shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of the goods and services of any place of public accommodation without discrimination or segregation on the ground of race, color, religion, or national origin; and § 201 (b) defines establishments as places of public accommodation if their operations affect commerce or segregation by them is supported by state action.” Katzenbach. v. McClung, 379 U.S. 294, 298 (1964). In effect, the Court had to address the district court’s assertion that it was required to find a “demonstrable connection between food purchased in interstate commerce and sold in a restaurant and the conclusion of Congress that discrimination in the restaurant would affect that commerce.” Has Congress constitutional power to make such a law? . . . It is absurd to affirm that, because the rights of life, liberty and property (which include all civil rights that men have), are by the amendment sought to be protected against invasion on the part of the State without due process of law, Congress may therefore provide due process of law for their vindication in every case; and that, because the denial by a State to any persons, of the equal protection of the laws, is prohibited by the amendment, therefore Congress may establish laws for their equal protection. In fine, the legislation which Congress is authorized to adopt in this behalf is not general legislation upon the [civil] rights of the citizen, but corrective legislation . . .
D
E
Ž
I develop my argument about the materiality of the corporation, and the corporate use of nature as camouflage, more fully in
M
W
M
Lars Thøger Christensen & George Cheney,
Benjamin K. Sovacool,
E
S
Quentin Skinner,
T
Skinner,
N
J. G. A. P
H
Ž
A
Button v. Hoffman, 20 N.W. 667 (Wis. S. Ct. 1884); M
A
Constraints of space prevent me from addressing a concept that is, in any case, likely familiar to most readers, but, as many critics have documented—particularly with regard to the way the fascist state promulgated fantasies of an “organic” body of society—the nation-state often has been devised in conjunction with images of a unified, mass body.
R
Newman v. Vicksburg & M. R. Co., 64 Miss. 115, 122 (Miss. 1886).
St Louis Gaslight Co. v. City of St Louis, 84 Mo. 202, 204 (Mo. 1884).
Nw. Union Packet Co. v. Shaw, 37 Wis. 655, 660 (Wis. 1875).
McCarter v. Firemen’s Ins. Co., 74 N.J. Eq. 372, 381 (Ct. Err. & App. 1909).
Com. v. Copperman, 26 Pa. D. 763, 769 (Pa. Com. Pl. 1917).
Race Safe Sys., Inc v. Indy Racing League, 251 F. Supp. 2d 1106, 1108 (N.D.N.Y. 2003).
Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 558 U.S. 310, 348 (2010).
E
M
H
M
M
I address this dynamic of merging in full in “
M
M
John W. Myers & Ronald L. Jepperson,
P
F
Danny Hakim,
P
Citizens United, 558 U.S. at 364.
W
G
H
H
Barry C. L
H
I R
III R
R
VII R
VI R
X R
III R
III R
E
Emerson’s theory of self-reliance was misappropriated not via social Darwninism, as Howard Horwitz suggests, but by common misinterpretations that rely on generic and highly inapposite definitions of the self. For Emerson, self-reliance entails the evacuation of the individual self into an archetypal All or whole,--into a purely representative, typological, and finally corporate entity that eradicates false particularity. The transcendental corporate structure of agency Horwitz invokes is indeed Emersonian, but not because Emerson extolled individualistic exploits as they are commonly understood, but because for Emerson the transcendental individual is stripped of all individuality. The transcendentalist precisely transcends the self by merging into the divine aggregate, whether in Nature or the corporation. H
H
Our diurnal experience of the corporation inures us to systemic depersonalization. When a corporate on-hold message tells you “your call is very important to us,” it mocks your personhood; making such statements is akin to telling every person you pass on the street indiscriminately and mechanically that you’re in love with them. When I email Wells Fargo bank, I receive the following automated message: “Thank you for sending your service request to Wells Fargo. As one of our most valued customers, your questions and concerns are our highest priority.” These sentences were at some point written by a person (though a functionally illiterate one, since my questions are not one of their most valued customers). But the absurdity of sending a generic, automated reply that claims to initiate a personal relationship—that values you personally, or recognizes you—communicates the essence of the artificial intelligence of corporate personhood.
H
Peter d’Errico,
H
T
Davis-Floyd,
P
Thomas Frank,
J
John Dewby,
F
W
B
David S. A