Article Category: Article
Published Online: May 30, 2025
Page range: 40 - 48
DOI: https://doi.org/10.21307/connections-2019.060
Keywords
© 2025 Jan Fuhse, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
I was drawn to Harrison White’s theory of social networks, and to relational sociology around him from a rather Teutonic angle: My studies in political science left me disappointed about its ability to say much about the social basis, or the social embeddedness of politics, or even of the overall contours of the political realm. This pushed me into sociological theory, with first Jürgen Habermas, and later Niklas Luhmann, as guiding lights. Like Karl Marx and Max Weber before them, they were grand theorists: offering comprehensive and integrated theoretical mappings of the social world. This is what I was looking for: Theory that covers pretty much everything, with high levels of logical consistency and elegant conceptual arrangements. White’s theory is destined to disappoint on these criteria. Only I wasn’t able to see that from the start.
In the early 2000s, I started my doctoral research on Italian migrants in Germany. I wanted to apply Luhmann’s systems theory to collective identity phenomena like ethnic minority groups. However, systems theory could not help much: while elegant and cohesive, it remains mostly disconnected from empirical research. Basically, we are asked to believe Luhmann in his proclamations of the functional differentiation of society into subsystems, of the self-reproducing “autopoiesis” of these systems, and of the self-referential nature of communication. Similarly with Marx, Weber, and Habermas. So, to do empirical research, I had to look for other theoretical approaches. To supplant my systems theoretical starting point, or to complement it.
At that time, prominent systems theorists Dirk Baecker had come to praise White’s theory (1996). Like Luhmann, White does not start from individual actors, but what from the processes and social structures between them. And he offers an elaborate architecture of the social world. So, I dove into the first edition of
In spite of my fascination with the works of White, and with the work around him by Peter Bearman, Ron Breiger, Kathleen Carley, Paul DiMaggio, Roger Gould, Eric Leifer, Paul McLean, Ann Mische, John Padgett, Margaret Somers, Charles Tilly, and many others, I felt that I was missing something. What I thought of as a consistent theory left me with a number of puzzles. Why did everybody else know how to do network theory, and how to apply it, and only I could not figure it out?
In 2005, I decided that I wanted to meet the masters. Gathering my courage, I contacted Harrison White and Charles (“Chuck”) Tilly and asked them if I could spend 1 month at Columbia, to learn more about network theory. Both of them reacted supporting my research visit, and, together with Peter Bearman, also my later application for a postdoctoral fellowship from the Humboldt Foundation at Columbia. I came to spend first a month (September 2005) and then a year (May 2007–April 2008) there. I was fortunate to spend generous time with Harrison, even co-authoring a paper with him (and with Larissa Buchholz and Matthias Thiemann; White et al., 2007), and to take part in a variety of department activities and connect to many others (Chuck, Peter, Emily Erikson, Frédéric Godart, Joscha Legewie, Tammy Smith, etc.). Shortly afterwards, Chuck died after an extensive battle with cancer, and Harrison pretty much retired from academic work, and moved to Tucson, Arizona. I consider myself fortunate to witness the sunset of the golden age of relational sociology at Columbia.
However, I did not find there what I was looking for: the clear-cut, logically integrated theory of relational sociology simply did not exist. White had certainly tried to set it out in the two editions of
However, these do not so much form part of a coherent research enterprise, following a fixed set of theoretical ideas, laid out by White. Rather, relational sociology is united by a rough orientation toward similar research practices, and to common ideas of what to look for and study. Its studies share a few buzzwords—network, identity, story, and culture. But they frequently pick up on White’s theory only in passing, and very selectively. Partly, I would argue that this comes from its idiosyncrasy: Unlike most other theoretical enterprises, including Emirbayer’s, Erikson’s, Nick Crossley’s (2011), and my own (Fuhse, 2022) rendering of relational sociology, White develops a unique array of theoretical concepts that are very much his own, and not borrowed from earlier approaches: stories and identities, domains and netdoms, catnets, disciplines, switchings, and so forth. In the following, I discuss this uniqueness and idiosyncrasy of his theory:
I argue that, probably unknowingly, White followed the playbook of
I cannot substantiate these claims in full here. Instead, I sketch my position by pointing out the peculiarities of White’s position, and its adherence to positivist principles. The following two sections trace the development of White’s theory from catnets, structural equivalence, and blockmodels to the two editions of
As a trained physicist, White moved into the social sciences with an interest in the mathematical modeling of social structures. This contrasted with the grand theory of Talcott Parsons, dominant at Harvard where White took up the position of Associate Professor in 1963. However, Harvard also housed small group researchers George Caspar Homans and Robert Freed Bales, with whom he pursued his interest in sociometry. This may sound rather empirical, but the lecture notes of his student Barry Schwartz from White’s undergraduate course
With the connection to Homans, it would have made sense to term densely connected network partitions “groups”. But White insisted in coining his own term “catnet”, a neologism combining “cat” for category and “net” for network. This falls in line with White’s avoidance of theory texts in his seminars and in his general reading, focusing on empirical studies from history, anthropology, psychology, and organizational studies (Padgett, 2025). He did want to arrive at far-reaching general models of social structure, but without recourse to the established models in sociological theory from Marx to Parsons. Instead, theoretical notions and arguments are to arise out of the empirical observation of a wide range of social phenomena.
At about the same time, White worked on the formal-mathematic modeling of kinship relations (1963). This led to the concept of “structural equivalence”, advanced with mathematician François Lorrain (Lorrain & White, 1971). Kinship categories like “uncle” do not bound densely connected network segments, as in the catnet concept. Instead, they mark “structurally equivalent” positions in family relations: Uncles are united in their systematic relations to other kinship categories: aunts, parents, siblings, nephews and nieces, cousins, and grandparents. Again, White’s ideas center on the interplay between networks of social relationships and symbolic forms—kinship categories, in this case.
The notion of structural equivalence led to the method of blockmodel analysis with White’s Harvard students and colleagues, Scott Boorman and Ron Breiger. The famous blockmodel papers (Boorman & White, 1976; White et al., 1976) pick up on the concept of “roles”: The relations between structurally equivalent positions in networks are interpreted as role patterns. White and his co-authors here start from anthropologist Siegfried Nadel’s vision of social structures as systematic patterns of relations between roles. This has important parallels with the well-established concept of roles in sociological theory, as devised by Ralph Linton, Robert Merton, Talcott Parsons, Ralf Dahrendorf, and Ralph Turner. In principle, the two strands of literature can well be brought together (and combined with concept of “institution”; Fuhse, 2022, p. 133–163).
However, White and his co-authors simply ignore the sociological literature here. This leads, among other things, to a lack of reflection on whether role patterns emerge out of the interaction in network contexts, as among novices in a monastery. Or whether role patterns can also result from institutionalized cultural categories, as in kinship relations, or from the formal organization of the positions of, say, professors and students, and the relations between them, in a university. The empirical phenomena are bracketed from their wider social and cultural contexts; and the role concept denotes that which can be observed—without consideration of origins (and consequences).
During the 1980s, White became dissatisfied with the prevailing structuralist understanding of social networks (Mische, 2011, p. 82). Following graph theory, these were regarded as patterns of ties, without worrying too much about the nature of these ties, or about the differences between various “types of ties”. The blockmodel papers exhibit this basic stance of social network analysis:
The cultural and social-psychological meanings of actual ties are largely bypassed in the development. We focus instead on interpreting the patterns among types of tie found in blockmodels. Our sole assumption here is that all ties of a given observed type share a common signification (whatever their content may be).
The first edition of
However, White does pick up on abstract concepts in
The result is an idiosyncratic combination of different strands of literature, a “creative conceptual mess”, which opened up new ways of looking at social structures and the processes in them. White broke up old ways of thinking, pointed to conceptual gaps in sociology and network research, and offered fresh concepts and research questions. However, this also left many of us bewildered, sometimes even taken aback by this conceptual jumble—fascinating, irritating, and incomprehensible. It was impossible to fully grasp this theory bomb. Most of White’s disciples and students, including myself, adopted his framework only in parts, and often enough more implicitly than explicitly.
There were certainly alternatives for this “creative mess”: Symbolic interactionists had by then offered conceptualizations of social relationships and networks as patterns of meaning (Fine & Kleinman, 1983; McCall et al., 1970), and of identities as projection points arising in interaction (McCall and Simmons [1966] 1978). There was a budding research literature on social relationships (Duck, 1990), mostly hailing from psychology and offering both conceptualization and empirical studies (White’s treatise curiously missed empirical work on relationships). Exchange theory offered a plausible account of social networks based on the idea that exchange is based on obligations, and gives rise to them (Cook & Whitmeyer, 1992).
All of these approaches embrace that social networks consist of patterns of meaning, without White’s unwieldy concepts. They could have been combined with White’s ideas, as the next generations of relational sociologists did (Crossley, 2011; Emirbayer, 1997; Emirbayer & Goodwin, 1994; Erikson, 2013; Fuhse, 2022). Many of them resorted to the notion of “expectations” as key for relationships—with “stories” about events feeding into expectations, but with events bringing about expectations between ego and alter even without stories told about them. This makes for a more accessible conceptualization of social relationships that resonates with everyday experience. It also curiously ties network research back to the work of Parsons, who (building on Weber) conceptualizes social structures as patterns of expectations (Parsons et al. [1951] 1959, p. 19f). However, expectations remain fundamentally unobservable in empirical research—we can only infer them from observed behavior. Stories, in contrast, are told in communication. Here, as elsewhere, White prefers concepts to denote something observable, rather than mere theoretical constructions. This might also be the reason why he rejects subjective meaning and motivations as theoretical constructs, against the grain of the action theory, pragmatism, interactionism, and critical realism.
Things changed a bit with the papers published in the late 2000s and early 2010s, and with the second edition of
The above discussion already pointed to a few peculiarities of White’s way of theory-construction: the shunning of previous sociological theory (for a long time), the strong connect to empirical observations, with theoretical terms based on these observations, and the avoidance of unobservable theoretical constructs. Together, this follows the idea that theory springs from empirical work, to systematize and integrate it, and to guide future empirical studies. This may sound reasonable, but it is a textbook case of an epistemological approach most social scientists reject by now. My claim is that Harrison White’s theory, probably unknowingly, is a prime example of
This approach resembles the “positivism” Turner (1985) advocates, building on Auguste Comte: The task of social science is to assemble positive knowledge about the social world, based on empirical observations and their generalization. But the prime reference point is the philosophy of science school of logical positivism, springing from the Vienna Circle around Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, Herbert Feigl, Carl Hempel, and others. However, the writings of the original Vienna Circle are more complex and less united than typically presented (Friedman, 1991). The well-known position of logical positivism results at least as much from the sympathetic, but highly selective recasting by Ayer ([1936] 1990), and from the sustained criticisms by Karl Popper, Ian Hacking, and a diverse group of “post-positivists” as from the writings of the Vienna Circle. As in the theory of White, the identity “logical positivism” derives from the story-telling in academic discourse. Here are the main points of this position:
1. Logical positivism is thoroughly
White’s theory is empiricist throughout, with its many examples from empirical studies illustrating the concepts and theoretical arguments. He rejects “contributions [to science that] could not be overturned by any conceivable data” (White, 1980, p. 201). At the same time, he argues that “persuasion about definite features of the natural world is a distinct goal” of science (White, 1980, p. 199).
2. Positivism is
3. The flipside of positivism’s empiricism is a vehement
Again, this mirrors White’s stance, which starts from the rejection of Parsons’s structural-functionalism. He contrasts science with “rhetorics” as “its chief competitor” (White, 1980, p. 199). We can interpret rhetorics here in terms of the metaphysics derided by logical positivism: abstract verbose arguments that are not rooted in empirical observations: “rhetoric is the fashionable way of selling one’s nostrums” (White, 1980, p. 202). In the 2000s, White picks up on the theories of Bourdieu and Luhmann, with the latter containing a fair amount of metaphysics. It is not clear to what extent this changes White’s overall stance.
4. The logical positivist strict orientation to empirical research and rejection of metaphysics corresponds with an How are views of science evolving on the part of that very large body of persons known as women? [...] As persons who are women become known as persons of other sorts, the question will/should evaporate.
First, he challenges that women should unquestionably and primordially be regarded as “women”, rather than as persons in general. Second, White argues that “the female question” at least with regard to the belief in science should “evaporate” as more women become “persons of other sorts”, presumably entering formerly male dominions like politics, academia, industry, medicine, and commerce to be seen as politicians, professors, engineers, medical doctors, managers, and bankers. White here clearly advocates the
5. The empiricism and rejection of metaphysics leads logical positivism to
White’s theory displays the same disdain for unobservables: Most concepts in the first edition of
6. Logical positivism by and large adheres to the principle of
The issue of induction, or of the method of constructing theory in relation to empirical observations, has been extensively discussed in the philosophy of science. Karl Popper argues that building scientific theories through induction is impossible, not least because there are no pre-theoretical observations (1963, p. 59–72). Observations are always selective, they build on preconceptions of what to look for, and how to conduct them. Instead of going bottom-up from observations to theory, Popper suggests going top-down: We logically deduce propositions from theoretical assumptions, and then submit them to empirical tests. If empirical observations match these propositions, they are not verified (as in logical positivism)—that would be impossible. Instead, they are “not falsified” and provisionally accepted as true. The assumptions themselves are untestable. Rational choice follows this model of the scientific enterprise: Human beings are assumed to strive for the maximization of their subjective utility with their actions, and this leads to concrete propositions for how individual actors behave in particular situations.
In principle, I agree with Paul Feyerabend that we can arrive at good theory by any method (Feyerabend [1975] 2010). However, both induction and deduction suffer from the idea that either theoretical reasoning or empirical observation could proceed without the other. This idea has been refuted in successive waves, but decisively in the 1950s (Hanson [1958] 1965; Sellars, 1956; Quine, 1951). Quine points out that all scientific sentences carry both “analytic” (theoretical) and “synthetic” (empirical) implications. It is not possible to observe pre-theoretically, pace Popper. But theoretical reasoning is similarly always already informed by empirical observations. As a consequence, the strict separation between assumptions and conjectures does not hold: Assumptions start from empirical considerations (like the rational choice idea that human actors try to maximize their well-being), and may become subject to empirical tests with the right tools.
Also, following this principle, “metaphysics” cannot be discarded and rejected straightaway, as logical positivists and Popper would have it. All metaphysical speculation somehow rests on empirical observations, even if they are not methodically controlled (and also subject to theoretical pre-conceptions). Certainly, not all theory connects to empirical research to the same extent. However, even abstract theoretical schemes like those of Parsons and Luhmann are not wholly disconnected from the world of observations, and may yet become useful for empirical research.
What do these last deliberations mean for White’s theory? First, his disdain of previous sociological theory is misplaced. While White believed to work inductively entirely from observable facts, these are already shaped by theoretical preconceptions. The idea of theory-abstention, heralded by Geertz ([1973] 1993, p. 24–28), fails to realize: All observation starts from theoretical ideas, from concepts that researchers hold about their subject area. In White’s case, the theory builds on observations guided by the “structural intuition” of social network research (Freeman, 2004, p. 3): That social phenomena can and should be observed with regard to patterns of social relations, and that these networks are key for social behavior. Also, the concepts brought in from other disciplines do not come without theory: roles (from anthropology), stories, narratives, identities, etc.
As I argue above, there would have been alternatives from sociology—from symbolic interactionism, exchange theory, cultural sociology, role theory, and the sociology of organizations, even Parsons and Weber. These would have connected White’s theory to previous research strands, and made it a lot more accessible and acceptable in the discipline. The more recent generation of network theorists pursues this path, including myself (Crossley, 2011; Emirbayer & Goodwin, 1994; Erikson, 2013; Fuhse, 2022; Lin, 2002; Martin, 2009). On the upside, White gave theoretical reasoning on networks a fresh start: He brought in unique concepts and ideas building on other disciplines, and on his curiosity about a wide range of research on social structures. Key concepts like identities and stories, the intertwining of networks and cultural domains, and the role of linguistic forms and communicative process (“switching”) in networks are bound to shape our thinking about networks over the coming decades. As they make their way into more accessible accounts (by Emirbayer, Crossley, Erikson, and others), they lose some of their iconoclasm and idiosyncrasy, but they are still irritating and disruptive in the best possible sense: Here are some new ways to think about social structures, which lead to new ways of carrying out network research. That is no small feat, and we have Harrison to thank for it.
I offer a slightly different take on communicative process as “stitching” various socio-cultural contexts together, based on a casual remark by White (Fuhse 2023).
White offers a few remarks on the dangers to scientific rigor and on the reasons for an erosion of trust in science (1980). These inform my arguments but do not come close to outlining his epistemological position. Thanks to Ron Breiger for pointing me to this little-known but remarkable publication.