Pubblicato online: 16 giu 2022
Pagine: 153 - 171
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/bjals-2022-0003
Parole chiave
© 2022 Thomas Halper, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
For many English intellectuals, the years preceding the Second World War marinated in exasperation, resentment, and anger. (1) On the right, figures like T.S. Eliot bemoaned the erosion of traditional authority and its replacement with vacuous vulgarity. (2) On the left, figures like W.H. Auden bemoaned the presence of traditional authority and its vacuous vulgarity. (3) Neither camp much considered the everyday lives, hopes, and fears of ordinary people, so caught up were they in Deep Thoughts. George Orwell, though emphatically a man of the Left, was even more emphatically his own man. He regarded the preoccupation with ideological abstractions as not simply an inadequate path to understanding the world, but also a dangerous one; for in dismissing the value of the mundane and the specific, it opened the door to an arrogance that was thoroughly hostile to liberty and decency. Thus, he wrote books detailing the life of being down and out in Paris and London (4) or mining in Wigan, (5) and found time to praise suet pudding. (6)
This quotidian concern never leaves Orwell's
It is fair to ask whether Orwell's reflexive hostility to abstractions was carried too far. We do, after all, need some kind of overall theory or concept or prejudice to make sense from what otherwise would simply be onrushing disparate facts. If we do not openly acknowledge the theory, we may be guided by an implicit version we never bothered to examine, and that can hardly be a useful way to try to understand the world. Orwell, in his preference for the concrete, sometimes makes lists of things do the work of argumentation, gliding over the fact that a different list might support a different argument. Yet if he occasionally falls into this trap, his preoccupation with the tangible and the real works far more often as a bracing intellectual vaccine that wards off the inane and toxic ideas poised to attack us.
In
To today's reader of
Unlike most dystopias, which are chock full of gadgets, the telescreen is the only significant technology that Orwell introduces, and its very uniqueness highlights its importance. It molds the people through propaganda, including its two minutes of hate, but its chief value is intimidating them; the point is not that it observes everything they do, but that this is made public and drummed into them. It is the
Orwell's principal concern, which he developed in a number of essays that preceded
One of the first tasks of toddlers is to learn the names of things; they see a doll and convert the thought to “doll.” This guileless process, however, is not Orwell's concern. Instead, he focuses on the cynical thought that shapes language. “The first thing that we ask of a writer is that he shall not tell lies, that he shall say what he really thinks, what he feels.” (19) Thus, the writer's mortal sin of insincerity: American white supremacy packaged as the Southern Way of Life, the wealthy seeking to avoid taxes calling themselves job creators. The point had been made often, but Orwell's unadorned prose gives it an impact that is distinctive.
Yet for Orwell, as for Dewey, “Society not only continues to exist . . .
As Orwell wrote of Newspeak, a version of English invented by the Party, its purpose “was not only to provide a medium of expression for the world-view of and mental habits proper to the devotees of [the state], but to make all other modes of thought impossible. . . . literally unthinkable, at least in so far as thought is dependent on words.” (26) Thus, the normal rationale for language, communication, is subordinated to a higher purpose, control. (27)
We understand that government addressing the public, marketers reaching customers, parents entertaining young children, and a vast range of other speakers deliberately devise words and phrases for a vast range of purposes. But we are also comforted by the thought that no one created and thereby can control entire languages, that they develop as a kind of spontaneous, uncoordinated consequence of innumerable human encounters. But in
The language revision campaign is famously epitomized in a series of oxymoronic slogans, like War Is Peace. (29) What can this possibly mean? That war may be a necessary prelude to peace? That war produces a peaceful sensation? That only through war can peace be found? The answer sidesteps all circumlocutions. War and peace have been successfully redefined, so that they literally mean the same thing. The point is made elsewhere, when a Party member, O’Brien, holds up four fingers and asks Winston, the protagonist, how many he sees. Winston answers, “Four! Four! What else can I say? Four!” Whereupon O’Brien tortures Winston, who then utters the desired answer, “Five.” But O’Brien will have none of it. “You are lying. You still think there are four.” (30) The object is not to elicit the correct response, but to control the thought; Winston must not merely say five, he must believe five. Given scenes like this, it is no wonder that “Orwellian,” with its decidedly sinister overtones, is “the most widely used adjective derived from the name of a modern writer.” (31)
One device that facilitates thought control is the memory hole, literally a hole in the wall leading to a chute and then to an incinerator. The ministry of truth (that is, falsehood) uses the holes to destroy evidence, so that it can continually rewrite history in support of its current positions. Through this endless process of post hoc revision, the Party is always right. Indeed, it is right by definition. As he explained in
The implications for law, a chief means of social control, are plain. Law, in the words of a founder of the law and literature school of thought, “establishes the terms on which its actors may talk in conflict and cooperation among themselves.” (33) Judicial opinions, then, may be conceived as part of an ongoing conversation on the issues raised, and so concern with the language employed becomes a major element in analysis. In the light of Orwellian language, consider a pair of famous judicial opinions that (unintentionally) illustrate the abuses that attracted Orwell's ire.
The first opinion to be examined was written by Henry Billings Brown, perhaps the most famous forgotten justice in the history of the Supreme Court. He was born in the Massachusetts village of South Lee in 1836 into a prosperous Puritan family, in which, he later observed, “there has been no admixture of alien blood for two hundred fifty years.” (34) After a pleasant and uneventful childhood, he recalled, “I was naturally obedient, and when my father said to me one day, ‘My boy, I want you to become a lawyer,’ I felt that my fate was settled, and had no more idea of questioning it than I should have had in impeaching a decree of Divine Providence.” (35) He graduated from Harvard, attended Yale and Harvard law schools for a while, read law in Detroit, where he joined the bar and served as assistant district attorney and then briefly as a judge, when he reported that he “was glad to take refuge in the comparative repose of the bench.” (36) He returned to private practice and developed a specialty in admiralty law as applied to Great Lakes shipping, but confessed that his “health was giving way under the uncongenial strifes of the bar.” (37) In 1875, he secured a federal district judgeship. Benefitting from a well placed recommendation from an eminent colleague, Brown was appointed to the Supreme Court in 1890 and served until 1906, when declining health and the prospect of continuing to receive full pay at age seventy led him to retire. He died in 1913.
How, then, can we characterize Brown's judicial career? He was a judge of modest abilities and temperament. Though he served with such figures as Holmes, Harlan, and Field, he lacked their intellectual ambition and force of personality. A conventional pro-business Republican, Brown avoided confrontations—hence, his arcane specialization— and seems to have had a deferential, timid streak. He also appears never to have been interested in the question of race, though he lived through a time in which controversies over slavery, Reconstruction, Jim Crow, and the Ku Klux Klan consistently placed it high on the national agenda. A diary he kept during the Civil War contained no reference to slavery or blacks. (38) When as a federal judge after the war he spent an evening with the former president of the Confederacy, Jefferson Davis, Brown recalled, “I am bound to say that I never spent a more delightful evening. I found Mr. Davis a most courteous and agreeable gentleman of the best Southern type.” (39)
In 1896, Brown was assigned the majority opinion in
Plessy pointed out that in New Orleans, where he resided, in addition to blacks, there were (in the language of the day) mulattoes, quadroons, and octoroons, and these latter three groups enjoyed higher social status and dominated African American political life. New Orleans, in short, recognized a variety of races, (41) and Plessy, a light complexioned octoroon, was selected to test the law precisely because he epitomized “the arbitrariness of the [binary] classification.” (42) As he argued in his brief, it was often “impossible” to determine a person's race; (43) and in his case, Brown noted that “the mixture of colored blood was not discernable in him.” (44) If Plessy had not informed the conductor that he was black, in all likelihood he would have passed for white. (45) The Separate Car Act thus threatened people like Plessy, who enjoyed some privileges, rather than darker blacks, who enjoyed none.
How, then, asked Plessy, could assigning passengers on the basis of race be left to untrained conductors? What gave the question great practical importance, he contended, was that race operated as a proxy for reputation. Lighter skin was valued greater than darker skin because under slavery lighter skin African Americans were likely domestic slaves or free persons, while darker skin African Americans were likely field slaves. Reputation was a form of property; the conductor was clothed with the authority of the state; the conductor's action in calling Plessy colored, therefore, constituted state action that deprived him of property without due process of law in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. So went Plessy's argument. Plessy would have solved the problem by empowering the individual to determine his own race. (Ironically, he refused “to admit that he was in any sense or in any proportion a colored man.” (46))
The common law compelled carriers to serve everyone, provided they were orderly and could pay the fare, but granted carriers the power to assign seats. But was the common law superseded by the Fourteenth Amendment's equal protection clause? Brown saw no conflict. “The power to assign [a passenger] to a particular coach implies a power to determine to which race the passenger belongs,” (47) Brown cited ten cases in order to show that “statutes for the separation of the two races upon public conveyances was held to be constitutional.” (48) Upon examination, however, one of these cases did not involve race, (49) another did not involve trains, (50) two were decided before the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment (51) and none of the remainder raised constitutional issues. (52) The ten citations, which together appear impressive, all disappear upon investigation, but the point had been made.
In considering the role of the conductor, Brown ignored Plessy's assertion that racial assignment will not always be easy to do. He did not consider Plessy's racial plea for self-assignment, perhaps because it would have encouraged light complexioned African Americans to call themselves white. On the other hand, nor did he consider that Louisiana's practice of relying on the judgment of conductors would introduce an element of unrestrained discretion that would fatally undermine the presumed objectivity of the procedure. Brown seems to have regarded binary racial identification as a question to be solved by common sense; “a legal distinction between the white and colored races . . . is founded in the color of the two races, and . . . must always exist so long as white men are distinguished from the other race by color.” (53) As to “the proportion of colored blood necessary to constitute a colored person, as distinguished from a white person,” he would leave this “to be determined under the laws of each state and [and] not properly put at issue in this case.” (54)
In Brown's eyes, then, we all can distinguish between white and black (except, of course, in the case of Homer Plessy). Race, in this sense, is a fixed and obvious matter of biology, not a category created and enforced by people, and therefore inherently problematic, blurry, and shifting. Thus, assigning Plessy to a black car could not damage his reputation “since he is not lawfully entitled to the reputation of a white man.” (55) For Plessy, this was the common sense that tells us the earth is flat.
Plessy had also raised the issue in his brief of the Thirteenth Amendment banning slavery, calling segregation “a badge of servitude,” but Brown brushed off the contention as “too clear for argument.”
(56) In support, he cited the
After discussing the
Given the developments sweeping the South in the 1890s, would segregation metastasize to cover virtually every aspect of life? “The reply to all this is that every exercise of the police power must be reasonable,” said Brown, “and extend only to such laws as are enacted in good faith for the promotion of the public good, and not for the annoyance or oppression of a particular class.” (62) In short, mindless fear mongering that can safely be ignored. (63)
The rest of Brown's opinion closely followed that of the lower court. He observed that states are free “to act with reference to the established usages, customs and traditions of the people with a view to the promotion of their comfort, and the preservation of the public peace and good order.” (64) Certainly, segregation on trains is no more “unreasonable or more obnoxious” than congressionally mandated segregated schools in Washington, D.C. (65) Louisiana, therefore, is not unreasonable in concluding that racial segregation on trains serves these lawful ends. Brown did not inquire as to why segregation promoted the comfort, public pace, and good order of the populace. Was it simply that adhering to settled tradition, good in itself, produces these results? But, then, hadn’t the Civil War been fought to overturn the settled tradition of slavery? Or was the settled tradition white supremacy, in which case references to equality could be disregarded? Brown does not press Louisiana for an explanation, perhaps because he already knew what it would be.
Thus, Brown accepted Louisiana's contention that the law did nothing but legally formalize settled practice. In fact, however, the years preceding the passage of the law were ones of “flux and change [with] no consistent, thorough, and effective system of social control, legal or extralegal, governing relations between the races.” (66) Indeed, one observer wrote, “In Louisiana certain railway trains and steamboats run side by side, within a mile of one another, where in the trains a negro or mulatto may sit where he will, and on the boats he must confine himself to a separate quarter called the ‘Freedman's Bureau’.” (67) The state's Reconstruction constitution of 1868 explicitly stated, “All persons shall enjoy equal rights and privileges upon any conveyance of a public character,” (68) though it was replaced by a much less friendly constitution in 1879. In other parts of the South, whites and blacks rode “together and without a partition between them,” (69) and in Tennessee, whites who smoked or had second class tickets frequently rode in train cars reserved for blacks. (70) In short, the Louisiana law was enacted less to formalize accepted practice than to change and rigidify it.
For Brown, equal does not mean identical. Of course, in ordinary speech, that is exactly what “equal” means. Two plus two is identical to four. But nearly all laws classify people, and thus treat people in one category differently from those in another. A driver exceeding the speed limit will be treated differently under the law from one who does not. Similarly, in considering benefits, the Court has held that providing Chinese students with exactly the same education as was provided for white students would not meet the test of equality because white and Chinese students were different enough, so that they required a different kind of education if they were to achieve the same result. (71)
But when judges upholding segregation claimed that equal did not mean identical, they had something very different in mind. They were not suggesting that for historical reasons blacks required more resources to reach the same result, but on the contrary, that there was no point in providing more than the minimum amount; intellectually and temperamentally, blacks were considered unfit to make use of more than that, and pretending otherwise would only stoke frustrated ambitions and create divisions in an otherwise harmonious society. Thus, in these situations, inequality would be construed as equality; each race would be treated according to its strengths and limitations, in a word, equally. Differences would not reflect discrimination, but merely inherent differences between the races, justifying greater resources for one than the other. Which naturally raises the question of how much inequality will be tolerated and for what purpose? In the South, of course, the degree of inequality was very substantial, its purpose was to maintain white supremacy, and the advantage always lay with the white population.
But this does not implicate the Fourteenth Amendment's equal protection clause, Brown adds, because it refers only to political and civil equality, which the Louisiana law explicitly guarantees, and not to social equality; because black inferiority is so fundamental and obvious there is nothing government can do to remedy it. This distinction between civil/political rights and social rights was common at the time, and in support Brown cites
(72) a well known case,
Brown's opinion culminates in a passage that over a century later remains astonishing: “We consider the underlying fallacy of the plaintiff's argument to consist in the assumption that the enforced separation of the two races stamps the colored race with a badge of inferiority. If this be so, it is not by reason of anything found in the act, but solely because the colored race chooses to put that construction upon it.” (74) “Laws . . . requiring . . . separation [of the races] in places where they are liable to be brought into contact do not necessarily imply the inferiority of either race to the other.” (75) “Either race” – so whites should be reassured that segregation does not denote their inferiority. (76)
Why, then, would the colored race construe segregation as degrading? As a transplanted Northerner living in Washington, a Southern city, it could hardly have escaped Brown's notice that under segregation, blacks were almost universally treated as inferior to whites. They were expected to step off the sidewalk if a white person approached, never to enter a white person's house by the front door, always to be called by their first names. The inference was obvious. If somehow, all this bypassed Brown's notice, still there was Harlan's famous dissent: “Every one knows that the statute in question had its origin in the purpose, not so much to exclude white persons from railroad cars occupied by blacks, as to exclude colored people from coaches occupied or assigned to white persons. [It] proceeds on the ground that colored citizens are so inferior and degraded that they cannot be allowed to sit in public coaches occupied by white citizens.” (77) Brown did not even take judicial notice of slavery nor inquire as to the true, obvious purpose of the Separate Car Act.
In dismissing the underlying fallacy, Brown offers a counterfactual: “if the colored race should become the dominant power in the state legislature, and should enact a law in precisely similar terms . . . the white race . . . would not acquiesce in this assumption.” (78) The obvious explanation, which he does not entertain, is that it had always assumed its superiority; when a quarter century earlier found blacks able to wield power in Southern legislatures, whites did not regard this as a natural progression that merely put the shoe on the other foot. Indeed, Brown goes on to say, “If one race be inferior to the other socially, the Constitution of the United States cannot pit them upon the same plane.” In other words, if segregation marks blacks as inferior socially, it is not really because that is their inexplicable conclusion; it is because it is true.
Brown writes as if racial segregation is indistinguishable from gender segregation in bathrooms or age segregation in grade schools. Yet segregation was never about separation. Blacks and whites interacted more and lived closer together in the South than elsewhere in the nation. Instead, segregation was about power and the effective enforcement of white supremacy. (79) Did blacks consent to such an arrangement? The question never seems to have occurred to Brown.
Brown's opinion reads like a nineteenth century exercise in Newspeak. A reader dropped in from behind a veil of ignorance would have no inkling of the historical treatment of blacks in America. Slavery is barely mentioned; prejudice and the anti-black terrorism of the period in which it was written are omitted entirely. The law on its face favors no race, and we must take it at that. All this despite Brown's certainly having been old enough to remember slavery and the Civil War he lawfully avoided with a legal payment of $850. Was segregation, a system that singled out slaves and their descendants for special treatment, related to slavery? The question never arises. Did segregation entail an official judgment of black inferiority? In a perfect example of Orwell's insincere writing, Brown answers, only if blacks insist on seeing it this way (though elsewhere he admits that in this they are right), adding bogus precedents to prove it. It is as if all relevant history has been thrown down Orwell's memory hole and replaced by a fantasy of benevolent race relations Our ignorant reader could only wonder, stupefied, at Plessy's complaint, revealed as an eccentric act unmoored to reality, past or present.
In the end, we cannot avoid wondering whether history would have been substantially different had the Court decided Plessy in favor of Plessy. A few years later, in
Which brings us to William Orville Douglas, associate justice of the United States Supreme Court from 1938–1975. Can there be a less Orwellian judge than Douglas? Famously cantankerous, he was a notorious loner and iconoclast, who in nearly forty years on the Supreme Court seems to have developed no strong positive attachments to any of his colleagues. (81) Influencing their thoughts or playing at court politics, like, say, Frankfurter or Brennan, was foreign to his nature. It might be tempting to trace this to his hardscrabble childhood, which he described in best-selling memoirs (82) as poverty made worse by polio but overcome in time for military service in Europe in World War I, college, riding the rails across country to law school at Columbia, a professorship at Yale, the chairmanship of the Security and Exchange Commission, and an appointment to the Supreme Court at age forty, the youngest Justice since Joseph Story over a century and a quarter earlier.
However, we know, courtesy of a devastating biography, that the persona that Douglas carefully crafted was full of lies. He was not born in poverty; he never contracted polio; he was never on active military duty in Europe; he was no Depression hobo. (83) We also know that the common decency that Orwell celebrated found little echo in Douglas’ treatment of family and friends, in his womanizing and drunken binges, in his preoccupation with money, in his indifference to his children (despite an award as father of the year). Indeed, his life was littered with cruel, cold betrayals, as he discarded one relationship after another. Viewed from a distance, it is hard to imagine why someone apparently so little interested in the esteem of others would work so assiduously to concoct so false an image. Which suggests that Douglas may have been much hungrier for esteem than he liked to appear.
But our concern is not how or why Douglas constructed such a fake persona, but how this Orwellian pattern permeated his work on the Court. It is here that his cynical use of language is on display. Consider
After briefly passing on the question of standing, Douglas announced, “We do not sit as a super-legislature to determine the wisdom, need or propriety of laws that touch on . . . social conditions.”
(86) With this, he attempted to distance his opinion from the notorious
These cases he cited, he concluded, suggest that “specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have penumbras, formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life and substance.” (92) Though privacy is not mentioned explicitly in the Constitution, we can infer it, he said, from the First Amendment's freedom of association, the Third Amendment's prohibition against quartering soldiers, the Fourth Amendment's protection against unreasonable searches and seizures, the Fifth Amendment's self incrimination privilege, and the Ninth Amendment's broad reminder that not all rights are listed in the Bill of Rights. (93)
“The sole aim of a metaphor,” said Orwell, “is to call up a visual image.” (94) A penumbra, with its illumination from the sun mostly hidden by a lunar eclipse, clearly calls up a vivid visual image. (95) But is the metaphor helpful? Emanations flow from the entire circular penumbra, in other words, innumerable emanations flow from a single sun in innumerable, 360 degree directions. Douglas’ point, however, is precisely the reverse, not that the emanations are widely dispersed but that they all are concentrated and point to one thing, a right to privacy. The metaphor, in short, does not illustrate the phenomenon it is supposed to.
Ordinarily, too, metaphors use the familiar to clarify the unfamiliar. For example, we might say that an academic manuscript reads like a novel, that is, that unexpectedly it is easy and enjoyable to read. The metaphor works because we all know what a novel is. But “penumbra” is not a familiar term. In fact, its look-at-me quality may be exactly what Orwell meant, when he disparaged pretentious metaphors. The problem is not simply that they are snobby affectations; more importantly, their unfamiliarity is a deliberate distraction that takes our attention away from the subject at hand. Here, “emanations from a penumbra” is designed to divert us from noticing that none of the amendments cited is remotely related to the facts of the case. Nor does it address the retort that the Framers’ failure to mention a general right to privacy may have meant that they approved only the narrower rights Douglas listed nor that the Third Amendment had not been interpreted by the Court to apply to the states and so, did not belong on the list.
Nor, perhaps most seriously, does a reference to a right to privacy adequately define what the term means.
(96) Douglas’ usage implicitly suggested a widespread consensus, but even at the time the leading authority on torts had described the private law of privacy as consisting of no fewer than four distinct dimensions.
(97) Had the right been embodied in a constitutional amendment, judges could parse the text or examine its legislative history to determine the contours of its application. Clearly, it would forbid the government's reading my diary or videoing my morning shower without a warrant. But would it apply to a woman's right to choose to have an abortion,
(98) or one's right to decide when to die
(99) or to engage in homosexual sodomy?
(100) Without a text to guide it, the Court is on its own, for as Black noted in dissent, “’privacy’ is a broad, abstract and ambiguous concept.”
(101) Ironically, courts have generally shrunk from such broad grants of authority, perhaps from fear of generating a backlash. One reason the forgotten Ninth Amendment
(102) has been pretty much forgotten is that it offers no instructions on how courts should identify rights not enumerated in the Constitution. In
Douglas follows the emanations passage with a hypothetical of police storming the “sacred precincts of marital bedrooms” (104) in search of contraceptives, ignoring the fact that the Connecticut law had gone unenforced for generations and as if bedrooms had legal status as sanctuaries. If I were suspected of shooting my wife, would the police be barred from searching our bedroom? More pointedly, the facts of the case did not concern the use of contraceptives in a marital bedroom, but rather access to information concerning their use to be provided in an open forum. This, in turn, raises the question as to whether privacy can exist in public. (105) By disregarding the element of seclusion, was Griswold also renouncing privacy claims? It is an interesting question, but Douglas never paused to consider it. The bedroom hypothetical, in any event, appears to have been inserted to gin up outrage, but in truth was apropos of nothing.
The opinion closes with an
Douglas’ opinion is unencumbered with the conventional judicial focus on the facts of the case, the text of the statute and the Constitution, the relevance of precedents, and deference to lawmakers. Indeed, the entire opinion establishing a fundamental right in a controversial fashion consumed only six pages, of which two were devoted to the facts of the case and standing. This was by no means unusual for Douglas, who flouted convention in these respects, as he did in so many other aspects of his life. After barely a year on the Court, for example, he wrote a far reaching aggressively pro-government opinion in a tax case, (112) when even a friendly observer admitted, “there was little, if anything, in the statute to support it.” (113) His opinion was seven pages, of which nearly three covered a statement of the facts.
Whether termed free-wheeling or sloppy, Douglas’ approach to opinions granted him vast discretion in his result oriented arguments. What is obvious in
It will strike many as odd to pair
However, an exclusive focus on results hides an ends/means problem. We must concern ourselves not only with the decisions, but also with the paths to the decisions, for if they are not the right paths, they may in other contexts take us to destinations we would do better to avoid. Both opinions appeared when Orwell was not on the scene,
Meanwhile, ignored by both justices was the central question of the proper role of the unelected, unaccountable Court. Should it take upon itself the job of updating a Constitution it feels has become out of date? The Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments addressed the question as to the status of the freed slaves and their descendants. Many issues were left undecided, it is true, but returning blacks to a state of subjugation was clearly not the goal of the framers of the amendments. But by 1896 times had changed, and as we say today, it was time to move on. Reconstruction and the era of relative black freedom were dead and gone. Better, then, to adjust to the new Southern reality. Thus did Brown give the amendments an interpretation in
So, too, had attitudes on contraception changed by 1965, partly due to the revolutionary development of the birth control pill. The Connecticut law, which not even its advocates before the Court defended as sensible and up to date, lagged far behind. What, if anything, should the Court do about it? We might assume that if a law has fallen so out of favor, the normal workings of democracy will lead to its legislative repeal. And yet the law was still there. Does this suggest that it is not as out of favor as it appears? Or that its persistence reflects some flaw in the democratic process? Does the obvious importance of the law require the Court to intervene and rectify the anomaly? Or does its importance instead mean that its resolution must be found in the ordinary political process? For Douglas, the law was ridiculous, the Court had the power to get rid of it, and its very ridiculousness created an opportunity to make a larger point about the constitutional right to privacy. The obvious irony is that Douglas’ Orwellian manipulation of language is at the service of a value Orwell cherished, privacy
As we read
M
Orwell was troubled by Eliot's persistent “conscious futility.”
Orwell thought Auden spent the war “watching his navel in America.” G
G
G
G
Y
A
It has long been a cliché that in the West, particularly, the United States, the population is either anesthetized or distracted by its incessant, booming materialism. Alexander Solzhenitsyn,
Samuel D. Warren & Louis D. Brandeis,
Matthew 10:29.
O
Similarly, while Russian officials today offer perfunctory denials that their security service poisons dissidents, the fact that Soviet era toxins are used makes the point that opponents must beware. The brazenness is a most effective show of power.
J
Florence Lewis,
4 George Orwell,
G
J
Esther Inglis-Arkell,
Sarah Everts,
E
L
O
O
The Polish philosopher, Leszek Kolakowski, wrote of the Soviet Union, “At public meetings, and even in private conversations, citizens were obliged to repeat in ritual fashion grotesque falsehoods about themselves, the world, and the Soviet Union, and at the same time to keep silent about things they knew very well, not only because they were terrorized but because the incessant repetition of falsehoods which they knew to be such made them accomplices in the campaign of lies inculcated by the party and state.” 3 M
G
O
Geoffrey Nunberg,
G
J
H
1890 L
G
C
L
Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 541 (1896).
K
B
Memphis & C. R. Co. v. Benson, 85 Tenn. 627 (1887).
People v. King, 18 N.E. 245 (1888).
Day v. Owen, 5 Mich. 520 (1858); West Chester & Philadelphia R.R. v. Miles, 55 Pa. 209 (1867).
Chicago & Nw. Ry. v. Williams, 55 Ill. 185 (1870); Chesapeake, Ohio & Sw. R.R. v. Wells, 85 Tenn. 613 (1885); The Sue, 22 F. 843 (D. Md. 1885); Logwood v. Memphis & C.R. Co., 23 F. 318 (C.C. W.D. Tenn. 1885); McGuinn v. Forbes, 37 F. 639 (D. Md. 1889); Houck v. South. Pac. Ry. Co, 38 F. 226 (C.C.W.D. Tex. 1888).
S
Slaughterhouse Cases, 83 U.S. 36 (1872).
Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3. (1883).
S
Three years later, a unanimous Court found no constitutional problem in a school board discontinuing a high school for blacks, while maintaining one for whites, giving budgetary woes as the reason. The Court's opinion was written by Harlan. Cumming v. Richmond Cty. Bd. of Educ., 175 U.S. 528 (1899).
Henry C. Dethloff & Robert R. James,
G
La. Const. art. XIII.
C. V
Logwood v. Memphis C.R. Co., 23 F. 318 (C.W.D. Tenn. 1885).
Lau v. Nichols, 414 U.S. 563 (1974).
Brown, s
Roberts v. City of Bos., 59 Mass. 198 (1849).
A few years later, Justice Brewer noted that as the Thirteenth Amendment did not single out blacks, its ban on slavery “reaches every race [with] the Anglo-Saxon . . . as much within its compass as . . . the African.”
B
Giles v. Harris, 189 U.S. 475, 488 (1903) (Holmes, J.).
M
W
B
Gen. Stat. CT. §§. 53–32, 54–196 (1958 rev.).
An earlier effort to challenge the statute was rejected by the Court as insufficiently ripe. Violations of the law had been prosecuted only once, fifty-one years earlier, and there appeared to be a tacit agreement that this would not occur again. The Court seemed to have assumed that an absence of prosecutions meant that the law was ignored, but it might instead have signaled conformity so widespread that prosecutions were unnecessary, for example, laws banning cannibalism. Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497 (1961). Douglas dissented, maintaining that the law violated constitutional guarantees of free expression and privacy, which he located in the liberty provision of the due process clause.
Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 482 (1965).
Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905).
Pierce v. Soc’y of the Sisters of the Holy Names of Jesus & Mary, 268 U.S. 510 (1925).
Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390 (1923).
Orwell,
Though Douglas’ “penumbra” is the most famous use of the term, it had occasionally appeared in opinions in earlier years. Burr Henley,
Thomas Halper,
W
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 598 (2003).
B
Orwell, s
That it can is argued by William C. Hefferman,
Skinner v. State of Oklahoma
Orwell, s
Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972).
Helvering v. Clifford, 309 U.S. 331 (1940).
E
Arguably, the
One commentator located
Friedrich Nietzsche,