Pubblicato online: 21 gen 2021
Pagine: 171 - 200
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/bjals-2020-0025
Parole chiave
© 2021 Thomas Halper, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
Born into a life of intellectual and social privilege, where “the flowering of New England was almost a family affair,” (1) Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., as a young man was a bit of an idealist. As the nation was careening toward what William H. Seward was famously to call an “irrepressible conflict” between slavery and freedom, (2) Bostonians in the Holmes’ circle immersed themselves in the question of race. Holmes’ mother, normally reserved, was emphatic in denouncing slavery as evil and in lauding its antidote, abolitionism. His father, on the other hand, a renowned essayist, dean of the Harvard Medical School, and one of the nation's most prominent public intellectuals, disapproved of slavery but regarded it as a “physical act” to be accepted “to the minimum consistent with our existence as a united people.” (3) Some members of his monthly Saturday Club, however, like Hawthorne (4) and especially Emerson, (5) were committed abolitionists, and bright, young Holmes, who often mixed with his elders, (6) perhaps also felt their influence.
Years later, Holmes recalled that “in my day I was a pretty convinced abolitionist and was one of a little band intended to see [abolitionist] Wendell Phillips through if there was a row after the meeting of the Anti-Slavery Society just before the war.” (7) His closest friend at Harvard, Penrose Hallowell, whom he called “the most generously gallant spirit [and] the greatest soul I ever knew,” (8) had volunteered for the underground railroad. (9) Holmes could easily have avoided service in the Civil War with a $300 payment his family could have afforded without difficulty, but, encouraged by his mother, he withdrew from Harvard and enlisted. (10) When he learned that his unit would be based in Boston, he transferred to another that saw combat, the Twentieth Massachusetts Voluntary Infantry, which suffered more combat deaths than nearly any other unit in the army. A Boston abolitionist, recalling the euphoria of the day, said that “it was as if one had learned to swim in air, and were striking out for some new planet.” (11)
Yet at a Memorial Day speech nearly twenty years after the war, Holmes remembered thinking only that “slavery had lasted long enough,” (12) possibly the most tepid condemnation imaginable from a writer whose “words were feathered arrows, that carried to the heart of the target, from a mind that searched and saw.” (13) The “issue of slavery [had] captured Holmes’ attention” (14) and sent him on to war, but the abolitionist commitment was not rooted in personal experiences with slaves or free blacks nor did it even induce him to avoid relationships with Southerners at Harvard from slave owning families. He later recalled of his generation that “our hearts were touched with fire,” (15) but in truth it was a kind of kindling that quickly burned itself out.
Nonetheless, Holmes’ war experiences were transformative, leaving him with “more cold steel in his make-up. (16) “I am not the same man (may not have quite the same ideas),” he wrote his mother after the Overland Campaign. (17) He was seriously wounded three times, very nearly died from dysentery, and saw his best friend, Henry Abbott, killed in action. The ignorance and stupidity of some of his commanding officers – an ignorance and stupidity that many soldiers and friends of his paid with their lives – left him shaken. “I see [a] youthful lieutenant . . . when I looked down the line,” he recalled. “The advance was beginning, we caught each other's eye and saluted. When next I looked, HE WAS GONE.” (18)The Battle of Ball's Bluff made an especially heavy imprint. Union soldiers were surrounded on three sides by Confederates and on the fourth by a sheer cliff overlooking a swift flowing river. The result was a massacre that left Holmes shot and contemplating taking poison his father had given him, if facing death. “I made up my mind to die,” he wrote his mother, but having passed the test for combat valor, he boasted, “I felt and acted very well and did my duty, I am sure.” (19) Everywhere were men struggling to fight and to survive, all for no real purpose, and randomness so often seemed to determine life, death, injury. At one point in the war, he wrote home, “As you go through the woods you stumble constantly, and if after dark perhaps tread on the swollen bodies already fly blown and decaying, of men shot in the head, back, or bowels.” (20)
By the time of the Emancipation Proclamation in 1863, which his mother hailed emotionally, he dismissed her high spirits and spoke of the fighting that lay ahead. In 1864, he wrote home that he had “felt for some time that I didn’t any longer believe in this being a duty.” (21) He had had enough of the war, perhaps suffering from undiagnosed post-traumatic stress disorder. (22) By this time, he had drifted away from Hallowell and become close friends with Abbott, a courageous soldier (“In action he was sublime” (23)), who flaunted his contempt for abolitionists and blacks. He recalled Abbott's “splendid coolness,” (24) and later celebrated a soldier's faith “to throw away his life in obedience to a blindly accepted duty, in a cause which he little understands, in a plan of a campaign of which he has little notion, under tactics of which he does not see the use.” (25) But this was not his way. He wrote his mother that “I can no longer endure the horrors of the line. . . . war demoralizes me. . . now I honestly think the duty of fighting has ceased for me.” (26) When his three year enlistment ended, he returned to Boston. “I started in this thing as a boy,” he wrote, “and am now a man.” (27)
Back home, Holmes found that his idealism had peeled away like bruised skin off a fruit. “The law had broken down in America,” wrote Edmund Wilson, and “the Constitution had gone to pieces. It was impossible for an honest man of Holmes’ probing intelligence to pretend that the law was a sacred code, which had simply to be read correctly.” (28) Louis Menand thought that the war had caused Holmes to “lose his belief in beliefs,” (29) but that is not exactly so, for what remained was a belief, really a fixation, on struggle. As Holmes, Sr. had observed, “Every now and then a man's mind is stretched by a new idea or sensation and never shrinks back to its former dimensions.” (30) Holmes, Jr.'s new idea, as he expressed it in an 1873 article, was that “the struggle for life [is] the law of human existence,” (31) an idea that seemed validated by his war experiences and the now potent theory of evolution.
But where the typical Social Darwinists of his day imagined that the struggle led inexorably to the improvement of the race, Holmes believed that the randomness of life meant that the results might be negative as well as positive. (32) In his eyes, the optimists’ assumption was simply an act of faith, bereft of evidence. All one could say for certain was that struggle led to more struggle. Beyond that, it was hard to know where it led. But Holmes did not collapse in existential despair. For him, as for Nietzsche, the discovery of truth may be beyond human capacity, but we can at least honor the will to struggle for individual autonomy and greatness. (33) For Holmes, this meant launching his legal career with enormous drive and ambition. Toward the world, though, he looked with his famous (or notorious) detachment: “If my fellow citizens want to go to hell I will help them,” he wrote a friend. “It's my job.” (34)
By the time he was a famous judge, Holmes’ abolitionism had quite evaporated. What remained was a distaste for its intensity and moral certainty. Indeed, he admitted that he “came to loathe in the abolitionists the conviction that anyone who did not agree with them was a knave or fool.” (35) He derided them for putting “their ideals and prophecies with the slight superior smile of the man who is sure that he has the future. . . . I can only say that the reasoning seems to me inadequate.” (36) They seemed to him like the temperance advocates of prohibition. (37)
By this time, too, the Civil War's goal of freedom for the slaves had in peace time turned to ashes. Legally required racial segregation, augmented by violence and terror, had enshrined white supremacy in the South and left the black population in poverty and subjugation. Most whites in the North hardly seemed to notice, but not Holmes. To complaints about the Sacco and Vanzetti trial, for example, he answered, “If justice is the interest why do they not talk about the infinitely worse cases of the blacks?” (38) And again, “A thousand fold worse cases of negroes come up from time to time but the world does not worry over them.” (39)
Holmes’ service on the Supreme Court, particularly in the first two decades or so, coincided with an explosion of race riots that inflicted heavy losses in life and property, almost exclusively on blacks. In the South, riots took place in Pierce City, Missouri (1901); Statesboro, Georgia (1904); Atlanta (1906); Houston (1917); Elaine, Arkansas; Jenkins county, Georgia; Charleston; Longview, Texas; Washington; Norfolk; Knoxville; and Annapolis (1919); Ocoee, Florida (1920); Tulsa (1921); Perry, Florida (1922); and Rosewood, Florida (1923). At the same time, rioting also occurred in the North at Denver (1901); Evansville, Indiana (1903); Springfield, Ohio (1904 and 1906); Greensburg, Indiana (1906); Springfield, Illinois (1908); East St. Louis, Illinois (1917); and Indianapolis and Omaha (1919). DuBois had predicted that the “problem of the twentieth century is the problem of the color line.” (40) Holmes might have been vaguely aware of that. Consider his voting and opinion record on the race related cases decided during his tenure on the Supreme Court.
Holmes, speaking for a five-four majority, refused to grant relief. If the “whole registration scheme of the Alabama constitution is a fraud upon the Constitution of the United States,” he asked, “how can we make the Court a party to the unlawful scheme by accepting it and adding another voter to its fraudulent lists?” (45) Even if the Court issued an order, he added, “the great mass of the white population intends to keep the blacks from voting.” Hence, if “the conspiracy and the intent exist, a name on a piece of paper will not defeat them.” (46) Relief would require the Court “to be prepared to supervise the voting,” (47) which lay far beyond its powers. Instead, relief “from a great political wrong, if done, as alleged, by the people of a state and the state itself, must be given by them or by the legislative and political department of the United States.” (48)
White, again speaking for a unanimous Court, held that the 1868 provision clearly violated the Fifteenth Amendment, (53) and that the other two requirements also must be dropped because together they meant that a native born citizen had to meet a property qualification, while a naturalized citizen did not, an “incongruous result” (54) that made no sense.
Holmes, writing for a seven-one majority thought it was obvious that words that banned conspiracies to prevent blacks from voting also covered not counting their votes. (56) The Klan might “have passed away,” but regardless of what Congress intended in the law, “we cannot allow the past so far to affect the present as to deprive citizens” of their legal rights.” (57) In the course of his opinion, he dismissed a technical argument tying a provision of the statute to a provision of an earlier statute. (58)
The Houston Democratic Executive Committee, on the theory that the party is a private organization like a bowling league, barred blacks from voting in the local Democratic primary. C.N. Love, a black Houston journalist and a Democrat, sought an injunction to forestall the election on the ground that the committee had violated his Fifteenth Amendment right against racial exclusion in voting. Love lost, and was ordered to pay court costs.
Holmes, speaking for a unanimous Court, conceded that Love's complaint could “present a grave question of constitutional law,” but observed that the committee's action covered only “a single election,” and that as the election had taken place a year earlier, “the cause of action had ceased to exist.” (59) Thus, mootness saved the Court from confronting the issue on its merits – Holmes was unimpressed by the argument that court costs remained a live issue – and no dicta were offered on the constitutional question.
Holmes, again writing for a unanimous Court, dismissed the state's argument as “little more than a play upon words” (61) because political actions that result in private damages may be resolved in lawsuits. It was not necessary to reach the Fifteenth Amendment issue, he said, as “it seems to us hard to imagine a more direct and obvious infringement of the Fourteenth. . . . [I]t is too clear for extended argument that color cannot be made the basis of a statutory classification affecting the right set up in this case.” (62)
In four of the six cases involving voting rights, Holmes supported the black plaintiffs, but in the two most important cases, his record is mixed. On the one hand is
Holmes also seemed intimidated by the fact that “the great mass of the white population” (65) meant to disenfranchise blacks. Certainly, it was obvious that disenfranchisement was the purpose of the provision. The president of the Alabama constitutional convention had declared its goal to be “to establish white supremacy in the state,” (66) and black voter registration in Alabama had declined from 93% in 1896 to 2.9% in 1902. (67) Holmes acknowledged as much. The question was: how should the Court respond? Overcome with a sense of the Court's powerlessness, Holmes feared that an order to open the voting would be disobeyed, humiliating the Court and perhaps emboldening future litigants to flout its authority. (68) His assumption of overwhelming support for black exclusion, however, may be open to question. The constitution was adopted only because Black Belt counties voted overwhelmingly for it; the rest of the state rejected it. As the Black Belt counties had a large black population and would hardly have supported its own disenfranchisement, it was commonly believed that there had been widespread voter fraud. (69)
Holmes’ decision, said to “wed legalism to realpolik,”
(70) has been derided as a “cynical and disingenuous” avoidance of the constitutional question,
(71) and a “carte blanche to southern politicians.”
(72)Derrick Bell, one of the most prominent civil rights advocates of his day, thought the ruling amounted to “judicial abstention with a vengeance.” Yet, Bell continued, “what alternative did Justice Holmes have available? [A] court's power to issue and enforce orders is limited to those orders that at least a substantial percentage of the people want or will permit to be carried out.”
(73) There was an alternative near at hand, however, though not a very satisfying one: accept Alabama's technical arguments, refuse to reach the merits, and deny giving discrimination the Court's tacit approval. This, of course, is exactly what Holmes chose to do in
On the other hand, in
Peonage, involuntary servitude in payment of debt, was outlawed by Congress in 1867.
(78) Among the first cases to arise under the law
(79) was
Justice Brewer, speaking for a unanimous Court, observed that the Thirteenth Amendment does not require state action, and so the law's applying to private conduct did not render it unconstitutional. But he could find “not a scintilla of testimony to show that [the men] were ever theretofore in a condition of peonage.” (80) That is, Clyatt was charged with returning the men to a state of peonage, but the government had failed to demonstrate that their condition before they were captured was one of peonage. Thus, Brewer ordered a retrial, in the meanwhile releasing Clyatt from custody.
Justice Brewer, writing for a seven-two majority, noted that the blacks claimed to have been mistreated because of their race, the mistreatment constituting a badge of slavery. It was, therefore, irrelevant from their perspective whether they personally had ever been slaves. Brewer found this argument fallacious. For one thing, the Thirteenth Amendment's prohibition against slavery “reaches every race,” with “the Anglo-Saxon . . . as much within its compass as . . . the African.” (81) Thus, blacks could claim protection of the Thirteenth Amendment no more than anyone else, and the fact that none of them beaten by Hodges had “ever been themselves slaves or . . . the descendants of slaves” (82) became very relevant, indeed. The amendment, Brewer maintained, may have permitted Congress to deal with “incidents or badges of slavery,” (83) but this referred to legal acts only, and thus did not apply here. The Thirteenth Amendment “is not an attempt to commit that race to the care of the nation,” (84) and so Brewer advised blacks that “their best interests would be subserved [by] taking their chances with other citizens.” (85)
Holmes, writing for the seven-two majority, held that there “is no doubt” (86) the state can punish fraud. He conceded that “it appears that [Bailey] was held for trial on the statutory evidence and with no other proof of fraudulent intent,” but insisted that Bailey was being punished for fraud and not for breach of contract. He thought that there was no reason to reach the question of the presumption's validity because “it may be that the prosecution will not rely on the statutory presumption but will exhibit satisfactory proof of a fraudulent scheme.” (87) Even “if that evidence was insufficient,” he continued, “it hardly will be contended that this Court should require the state courts to release all persons held for trial, where in its opinion the evidence fails to show probable cause.” (88) The two provisions, in any event, were separable. “The trouble with the whole case is that it is brought here prematurely by an attempt to take a short cut,” (89) and to free Bailey in advance of the trial.
Bailey was subsequently tried, convicted, and sentenced to 136 days of imprisonment at hard labor. Following Holmes’ implicit instruction to bring his action after his conviction, Bailey then appealed the conviction, by which time the Supreme Court had somewhat changed in personnel. Both he and the U.S. attorney general in his brief emphasized that peonage laws were almost entirely targeted at Southern black farm laborers.
The second
Holmes, dissenting, agreed that the fact that it was an Alabama case concerning blacks “does not matter.” (93) The law did not punish breach, he maintained, but only fraud, and the presumption that breach meant fraud could be disregarded by jurors with “experience as men of the world,” (94) if the evidence warranted it. As for criminalizing the punishment, he wrote, “it does not strike me as an objection to a law that it is effective. If the contract is one that ought not to be made, prohibit it. But if it is a perfectly fair and proper contract, I can see no reason why the state should not throw its weight on the side of performance.” (95) “Breach of a legal contract without excuse,” he declared, “is wrong.” (96)
Justice Day, striking down the Alabama law, emphasized that the debt was owed to the surety, not the state, which merely enforced it, and thus the case was a classic instance of peonage, which Congress could prohibit. Criminalizing debt assumed that the obligation to pay was a duty owed the public, as well as the private creditor, but traditionally, debt was considered a private obligation, and thus not to be criminalized. Day's focus was on repeat offenders, like Rivers, who were “kept chained to an ever-turning wheel of servitude.” (97) No mention was made of race.
Holmes, concurring, characterized the victims of peonage as “impulsive people with little intelligence or foresight,” (98) whose moral defects would lead them repeatedly to breaches of contract.
In these cases, Holmes is indifferent if not hostile to the incontrovertible fact that peonage laws were a tool for keeping Southern blacks in bondage. In
Similarly, in
In the second comment, Holmes thought it self-evident that the state should be able to hold persons for trial in the absence of probable cause, as if white Alabama juries would be likely to disregard a presumption of fraud attaching to black laborers. Indeed, there is something odd about a Boston Brahmin referring to white Alabama farmers as “men of the world,” as if, untouched by prejudice, they had only recently returned from a grand tour of
Speaking for a seven-two majority, Justice Brewer rested his opinion on the college's corporate charter. Kentucky's constitution empowered the state to amend corporate charters, so long as the original purpose of the charter was not defeated or substantially impaired. As Berea's existing charter, very general and brief, failed to refer to integrated education, the college could not claim that barring integration posed a fatal conflict. Neither party had argued charter revision in its briefs. (107) Harlan, dissenting, took for granted that integration was a harmless purpose, although the legislature, fearing race mixing and miscegenation, clearly took the opposite position.
Holmes registered a concurrence without an opinion.
Chief Justice Taft, speaking for a unanimous Court, citing a dozen state cases and two federal district court cases, said that the validity of segregated schools had been decided “many times.” (112) He concluded that “The decision is within the discretion of the state in regulating its public schools, and does not conflict with the Fourteenth Amendment.” (113) Segregation was a closed issue not open for debate.
Holmes’ record on educational segregation is passive. In
As to
The Court, by a vote of eight to one, found for the railroad. Justice McKenna observed that “the interstate commerce clause does not constrain the actions of carriers. But on the contrary leaves them free to adopt rules and regulations for the government of their business.” The rules must be reasonable, of course, but that is no problem in this case.
(115)
The Supreme Court unanimously rejected her contention, Justice Van Devanter observing that the “manifest purpose [of the Civil Rights Act] was to enact a law which would have a uniform operation wherever the jurisdiction of the United States extended.” (119) Congress would never have adopted a law that applied only in these narrow conditions. It “is not possible to separate that which is constitutional from that which is not,” (120) and so with the remainder of the act declared unconstitutional, her argument failed.
However, as none of the complainants ever traveled on the railway, they lacked standing and the suit was dismissed. Had the question of standing been addressed at the outset, where normally such questions are resolved, Hughes’ insistence on the railway's meeting its separate but equal obligation would never had been written. But as the circuit court had addressed the merits, finding that “quality of service . . . does not require permanent provision of service, irrespective of the demand for it,” (123) Hughes had an excuse to confront the merits, and it seems that he embraced the excuse with enthusiasm. By addressing standing at the conclusion of his opinion, he made the dicta prominent, and indicated a future path for the Court. In looking at the decades long process of destroying separate but equal, this case, which for the first time took “separate but equal” seriously, deserves pride of place as the initial judicial attack on Jim Crow, and is an excellent example of Hughes’ political sagacity at work.
Holmes joined three Southern Justices (White, Lamar, and McReynolds) in concurring without an opinion.
Justice McKenna, speaking for a six-three majority, held that the “regulation of the act affects interstate business incidentally and does not subject it to unreasonable demands.” (125) The railway was chartered in Kentucky, and therefore the law regulates the charter and “is not a regulation of interstate commerce.” (126) Finally, McKenna emphasized the “necessity, under our system of government, to preserve the power of the states.” (127)
In
In
As to
Prior to 1910, there had been little migration of Southern blacks to border or Northern cities, but drawn by a labor shortage that generated higher wages, black migration at this point began to change. (130) Activated by white economic and social fears, a number of cities, including Louisville, adopted ordinances that barred whites and blacks from occupying houses on blocks where the majority was of a different race. Charles Buchanan, a white real estate agent, and William Warley, a black home buyer, signed an agreement to purchase a house on a majority white block. Warley declined to complete the purchase when he learned that the ordinance would prevent him from occupying the house, complaining that the law negated specific performance of a real estate contract he had signed. Louisville countered that the law was intended “to prevent conflict and hostility between the white and colored races . . . and to preserve the public peace and promote the general welfare.” (131)
Justice Day, speaking for a unanimous Court, conceded that “there exists a serious and difficult problem [of] race hostility,”
(132) but concluded that the ordinance deprives buyer and seller of their due process property rights.
(133) The law may have been directed only at occupancy, but its connection to buying and selling was obvious. Nor could the law be justified by the goal of racial purity, for it permitted widespread interracial contact.
(134) Nor could it be justified in terms of maintaining whites’ property values, as undesirable whites were not prevented from moving to the block.
(135) Day distinguished the case from
The Supreme Court heard
Two nineteenth century cases might have provided powerful precedents for later jury exclusion cases. First, in
Holmes, relying on the South Carolina Supreme Court ruling, held in a brief opinion that the allegations were controverted, but the evidence submitted by Brownfield was not agreed to by the judge. (150) In the absence of proven allegations, the Court affirmed the lower court's ruling.
Holmes, speaking for a unanimous Court, wrote that the motion asserting a “constitutional right . . . cannot be withdrawn for prolixity . . . under the color of local practice.” (151) Rogers raised a federal question. The judgment was reversed, and the case remanded.
Justice Brewer, speaking for a unanimous Court, denied the appeal, writing that “actual discrimination . . . must be proved or admitted,”
(152) but all that was offered was an “affidavit of the defendants . . . stating that the facts set up in the motion were true” to their best knowledge, information and belief.
(153) As with
In a brief opinion, Justice Harlan, speaking for a unanimous Court, ruled for Texas, citing the “absence of such proof [required for] overcoming the denial on the part of the state.”
(154) As with
Chief Justice Fuller, in a brief opinion for a unanimous Court, observed that Thomas had raised a question of fact, and that “the ordinary rule is that questions of fact will not be reviewed by this Court on writs of error to state courts.” (156) He conceded that the Court might intervene, when “these decisions constitute such abuse as amounted to an infraction of the federal Constitution, which cannot be presumed, and which there is no reason to hold on the record before us.” (157) He pointed out that the grand jury contained a black juror and that “there were negroes on the venire from which the jury which tried the case was drawn, although it happened that none of them were drawn out of the jury box.” (158)
Speaking through Justice Day, the Supreme Court again insisted on proof that officials in charge of jury selection intended to exclude blacks, and upheld the conviction. (160)
Holmes’ contribution to jury selection jurisprudence was modest. He wrote only the
Chief Justice Fuller, in a brief opinion for a unanimous Court, quashed the writ on the ground that Riggins had asked the Court “to decide questions in advance of final adjudication, contrary to the settled rule.” (163)
In an opinion for a unanimous Court, Holmes announced that it was absurd to imagine that “a general denial and affidavit should dispose of the case.” (164) Holmes added that Johnson had been detained “to abide the further order of this Court,” (165) and so the sheriff, though a county employee, was acting as a federal officer. The Court, therefore, had jurisdiction to hear this case and to try Shipp for contempt of court. Holmes was clearly outraged that Shipp had characterized the opposing arguments as “frivolous.”
In the contempt trial, the only criminal case ever tried before the Supreme Court, Chief Justice Fuller in an unusually long and detailed opinion concluded for a five-three Court that “Shipp not only made the work of the mob easy, but in effect aided and abetted.” (166) Shipp was held in contempt.
Though lynching was commonplace during this period, its cruelty, bigotry, and denial of the rule of law all suggest that the Court would find it uniquely abhorrent. Holmes, as a young man, had described it as almost an irresistible force that “listens to no argument, for it is very little more than a mere animal movement. One might as well reason with a she-bear from whom he had stolen her cubs.”
(167) The opinions in both
A pair of cases involving race produced unanimous opinions with which Holmes silently joined.
It is easy from the moral perch of 2020 to condemn Holmes’ record on race compiled a century or more ago. In its general indifference to the claims of African Americans, it is inarguably appalling. One might answer that in in those times, whites, North and South, were for the most part indifferent to these claims. One might add that under the Fuller Court (1888–1910), every civil rights case except those involving lynching was decided against blacks, typically on technical grounds, with no reference to the overarching fact of violence, terrorism, and discrimination to which this sizable portion of the population was subject. One might also point to the prevailing judicial rhetoric of rights that tended to favor the interests of the strong against the weak. (170) There is no evidence that the Court ever considered taking judicial notice of the devastating consequences of Jim Crow that were present for all to see. In short, it might be said in Holmes’ defense that he was simply a man of his time, and that his actions (or inactions) reflected this fact.
Except that Holmes was not simply a man of his time. Edmund Wilson pointed to Holmes’ “unshakable self-confidence, his carapace of impenetrable indifference to current pressures and public opinion, [his] Brahmanism, his high-minded egotism, and his philosophical temper of mind [that] equipped him with impenetrable integument.” (171) Holmes, a proud iconoclast, delighted in swimming against the flow. A man of his time, for example, might have approved a crabbed commerce clause (172) or liberty of contract. (173) He did not. Or he might have approved national security rationales for suppressing speech. After an irresolute beginning, (174) he did not. (175) Indeed, in one of these cases, a delegation of three justices, joined by his wife, urged him to withdraw his stinging dissent in support of the speech rights of Russian Jewish communists. He paid no attention to them. (176) While Holmes appears to have been influenced by several young Progressives and their so-called House of Truth, (177) he was emphatically not a cypher blown by prevailing winds. He was stubbornly, if always politely, his own man.
It is difficult, then, to avoid the conclusion that Holmes was genuinely indifferent to the plight of blacks, particularly in the South, though for most of the year he lived in the Southern city of Washington and would have observed their discrimination daily. It was plain that each of the black litigants in the cases he heard were proxies for hundreds or even thousands, who for financial or other reasons were unable to make their pleas known. There is no sign that this troubled him. Similarly, though he often wrote about foreseeable harm, (178) he seemed blind to the obvious and intended consequences of the practices he voted to uphold. In this, he differed radically from his disciple, Frankfurter, whose emotional commitment to policies frequently clashed with his principled commitment to defer to legislatures. Holmes evinced none of Frankfurter's public agonies because he seems to have lacked the policy engagements. (179) In his voluminous correspondence, which often touched on current events, he almost never mentioned race, and one of the very few reform ideas he embraced was eugenics, which was then marinating in racism. If the status of blacks was not resolved as many of the abolitionists might have hoped, it was with few exceptions evidently resolved enough for him. (180)
Holmes’ response to the race question reflected his general view toward life. In this, society was not an organic whole, but merely the sum of individuals, each struggling to advance his own interests. The place of honor went to honor, that is, to the obligation to do one's duty, to fulfill the expectations inhering in one's position, for example, in the soldier's faith “to throw away his life” without hesitation or doubt at the command of his superior. Honor, in this sense, overlaps with authenticity, the obligation to be true to oneself for one's own sake. The ideal, then, would be an autonomous individual guided by rational deliberation, impervious to efforts at manipulation, and adhering to “an order which is inseparably indexed to a personal vision.” (181) What of the world around him? Holmes accepted the social order, but in innumerable comments made it clear that he regarded much of it as a façade concealing the ineradicable fact that “we may substitute free struggle for life.” (182)
In the end, so potent was Holmes’ preoccupation with being true to himself that it left little room for caring about others. Had Holmes believed human nature to be essentially cooperative and compassionate, perhaps the self-absorption might have proven more benign. But he dismissed all this as fantasy. It is not surprising, then, that the wounds from the Civil War, physical and emotional, did not sensitize him to the claims of injustice, though they did confirm his belief in evil and pain, not only as metaphysical constructs, but more pressingly, as dominant, supremely important practical facts.
Yet he did not dwell on the past, as Robert Burns wrote, “nursing her wrath to keep it warm.” (183) Holmes understood what he had lost—for example, the innocence, optimism, and idealism that had induced him to enlist in the army—was irretrievably gone, and that he could not return to his old self, in fact, that there was something weak and dishonorable about such nostalgic reveries. At the same time, his broad lack of interest in the personal past also meant that forgiveness, either as a practical accommodation or as a Christian virtue, did not concern him much. Indeed, when he contemplated venality (as he often did), it usually took the form of jaunty one-liners, not gloomy introspection, moral outrage or concrete action.
There was perhaps an element of self-flattery in this pose, for it presumed an elevated position far above the madding crowd. There was also perhaps an element of self-protection here, as if the casual indifference had calcified into a shield safeguarding him from the latent consequences of the trauma he had suffered decades earlier. Holmes’ rejection of a tempting preoccupation with the past was thus a sign of both practical adaptation and emotional maturity. No wonder he had no use for reformers, who seemed to deny the omnipresent fact of struggle and, as he said as a young man, “believe in the upward and onward—who talk of uplift, who think that something in particular has happened and that the universe is no longer predatory.” (184)
It is not surprising, then, that his youthful dalliance with abolitionism failed to remind him a half century later of the sorry plight of Southern blacks. Of course, there was the stentorian voice of his colleague, Harlan, to bring it to his attention. But Holmes did not think much of Harlan, writing that he has a mind like a “powerful vise the jaws of which couldn’t be got nearer than two inches to each other.” (185) His opinions, often full of moral condemnation, seemed to Holmes to parade virtue like a prize bull. “Certitude,” he wrote, “is not test of certainty.” (186) For Holmes, truth merely meant “that I cannot help believing it.” (187) Thus, was his ever-present arrogance married to a cosmic humility.
These attitudes informed Holmes’ vision of law and politics, as well. “The first requirement of a sound body of law,” he wrote in
It also logically leads to the position that courts should declare laws unconstitutional only when they cannot avoid doing so. The law may seem to a judge foolish, unworkable, even immoral, but these are not his proper concerns. These are matters for the lawmakers. The judge should ask only if the law is clearly unconstitutional. If it is not, questions of doubt should be resolved in favor of the lawmakers. For Holmes, for whom duty was of immense importance, this was how judges were obliged to act.
What is most striking is that while we take it for granted that great men seek after power, Holmes seems determined to limit that power. The great monarchs—Henry VIII, Peter the Great, Louis XIV—worked ceaselessly to centralize power in their own hands. Great presidents—Lincoln, Franklin Roosevelt—to a much lesser degree did the same. In ordinary speech, we may in fact conflate “great” with “powerful.” Holmes plainly does not fit the mold, and the explanation does not lie in self-doubt, a predilection to give in to others, or a temperament of overweening modesty, but rather in his sense of duty. On the issue of race, Holmes exhibited a level of deference that seems almost unthinking in its automatic consistency. His demands on lawmakers are virtually nonexistent. Within the Court, too, his role is largely passive, contributing few opinions and even declining to file lone dissents.
It was not difficult for Holmes to fixate on politics as struggle. As a bright son of intellectual Brahmans, as a wounded warrior in the Civil War, as a pathbreaking scholar in
From this perspective, as Judge Posner observed, “The democratic political process was merely the civilized, because non-violent, method of regulating the relative strength of the competing forces in society.” (190) Suppose the results favor only the short-term interest of the dominant forces? Suppose the results are indisputably immoral? Suppose the results are anti-democratic? Holmes is not insensible to these possibilities. He never romanticized what he called, as a young man, “the thick fingered clowns we call the people—vulgar, selfish and base.” (191) “I look at man through Malthus’ glasses—as like flies,” he wrote Laski, “here swept away by pestilence—there multiplying unduly and paying for it.” (192) Or as he wrote to Pollock, there is “no reason for attributing to man a significant difference in kind from that which belongs to a baboon or a grain of sand.” (193) There is hyperbole here, of course, but there is also a deep skepticism as to the wisdom and virtue of his fellow human beings and no illusion that democracy guaranteed good results.
This was hardly a secret to those who knew him. William James thought Holmes a model of “cold-blooded conscious egotism and conceit.” (194) James Bradley Thayer considered him “wanting sadly in the noblest region of human character—selfish, vain, thoughtless of others.” (195) Benjamin Kaplan (who only knew of him) labeled him “a tough old party, quite aware that he was deficient in empathy.” (196) Beneath his daunting charm and politesse, was Holmes unmistakably something of a cold fish?
Yet notwithstanding his evident disdain for ordinary people, Holmes as a judge was known for his reluctance to overturn laws enacted by the representatives of these ordinary people or even widespread unwritten customs. Time and again, he would insist, in Thayer's words, that he would uphold them unless they constituted “not merely. . . a mistake, but . . . a very clear one – so clear that it is not open to rational question.” (197) In case after case, he deferred to the legislature. (198)
“The life of the law,” in his mantra, “is not logic; it is experience.”
(199) He ridiculed those formalists, who imagined law “a brooding omnipresence in the sky,”
(200) emphasizing that it is created by real people to serve their purposes. Would Holmes inquire as to what these purposes were? Or was that none of his—and the Court's—business? But if he refused to inquire, how is law for him different from commands from thugs? Of course, lawmakers can point to a legitimate authority that thugs cannot. But do lawmakers retain this authority, even when they behave like thugs, for example, when they undermine their own democratic legitimacy by banning blacks from voting? In his classic
In the continuing tug of war between democracy and liberty on the subject of race, Holmes generally chose not to choose. When possible—and the Court usually contrived to find it possible—he preferred a decision on some technical ground that forestalled consideration on the merits. What makes this odd is his renunciation of formalism. “No one will ever have a truly philosophical mastery over the law,” he said at his Lowell lecture, “who does not habitually consider the forces outside of it which have made it what it is. . . . the law finds its philosophy . . . in history and the nature of human needs.” (203) If, as Judge Posner has written, “The character of legal formalism can be captured in such slogans as ‘the law made me do it’ or ‘the law is its own thing,’” (204) this is precisely what the Court and Holmes himself did in case after case, as they turned back challenges on peonage, educational segregation, transportation segregation, and jury exclusion on narrow grounds. When the topic failed to interest him, Holmes’ opposition to formalism was sometimes nowhere to be found.
Holmes’ habitual self-restraint clearly frees him from the charge of having been cursed by a hunger for power. Yet he was plainly smitten by the claims of vanity, as was evident in his “striking,” (205) look-at-me appearance—the old-fashioned shirts and collars, the huge white moustache that nearly covered his mouth. As a former clerk put it, “He cut a dashing . . . figure.” (206) Holmes might not have concerned himself with the opinion of the rabble of the hoi polloi, but after two decades of unearned relative obscurity on a Massachusetts court, he very much wanted the approval of intellectuals—perhaps, the same kind of intellectuals he had encountered in childhood congregating around his father. As Wilson observed, “It is Holmes’ special distinction . . . that he never dissociates himself from the great world of thought and art,” (207) that is, from a realm inhabited not by the lawyers and law professors that normally follow judges, but by the larger intellectual community. Advancing causes well established in these circles, like free speech or government regulation of business, would earn him plaudits for his bold sagacity, and his dissents in these areas have become legendary. As one Progressive wrote, “No judge who has sat upon the bench has been more progressive in his outlook.” (208)
On the other hand, safeguarding the interests of blacks, whom these same intellectuals had all but forgotten, offered no comparable rewards. Holmes did not want Harlan's Don Quixote mantel, which offered in place of adulation merely the label of self-righteous troublemaker. “Deep seated preferences,” he wrote, “cannot be argued about,”
(209) and what preferences seemed more deep seated than racism? Yet if Holmes were unwilling to argue about this preference, he was more than willing to argue about deep seated preferences concerning free speech or government regulation of business. “Congress cannot forbid all efforts to change the mind of the country,” he wrote in his much quoted
Holmes, unsurprisingly, would have an answer to all this. “Belittling arguments,” he once said, “have a force of their own,” (211) which reminds us that all of us (and not merely Holmes) are radically imperfect. “Out of the crooked timber of humanity,” in Kant's words, “no straight thing was ever made.” (212) Holmes remains a towering figure in American law: it was Holmes who breathed life into the First Amendment, (213) who battled liberty of contract (214) and a constricted construction of the commerce clause, (215) who modernized the takings clause, (216) who gave inspiration (217) to legal realism – and this impressive list is incomplete. Holmes was truly “a bridge between the old regime and the new order.” (218) On his retirement, Cardozo called him “the greatest of our age in the domain of jurisprudence; and one of the greatest of the ages.” (219) Even a modern critic conceded “there is something grand about the man.” (220) Yet Holmes failure to address the question of race with realism and compassion remains, beyond all doubt, a great stain on his reputation.
Philip Kurland,
W
O
Celebrating the outbreak of the Civil War, Hawthorne wrote that “it is delightful to share in the heroic sentiment of the time.” H
Looking back many years later, Holmes wrote that “the only firebrand of my youth that burns as brightly as ever is Emerson.” 1 H
On young Holmes as a conversationalist, see P
2 H
H
N
On the psychological importance of his enlistment, see Saul Touster,
T
O
F
G. E. W
H
Harry C. Shriver,
O
O
H
Holmes wrote his parents that “Many a man has gone crazy since the campaign begun from the terrible pressure on body and mind.”
O
E
M
O
Oliver W. Holmes, Jr.,
In his notorious eugenics opinion, Holmes ruminated on the fact that “the public welfare may call upon the best citizens for lives,” leaving the less fit to survive.
On Holmes and Nietzsche, see Seth Vannatta & Allen Mendenhall,
1 H
2
2
2 H
2 H
2
W.E.B. D
The cost and legal representation were secretly arranged by Booker T. Washington. August Meier,
A
Giles v. Harris, 189 U.S. 475, 482 (1903).
J. Gordon Hylton,
James v. Bowman, 190 U.S. 127, 139 (1903).
Guinn v. United States, 238 U.S. 347, 363 (1915).
Myers v. Anderson, 238 U.S. 368, 380 (1915).
Pub. L. No. 60-350, 35 Stat. 1088, 1092 (1909).
United States v. Mosley, 238 U.S. 383, 386 (1915).
Love v. Griffith, 266. U.S. 32, 34 (1924).
(1925) Tex. Rev. Civ. Stat. 3107.
Nixon v. Herndon, 273 U.S. 536, 540 (1927).
Richard H. Pildes,
It was said that President Wilson viewed the movie at the White House, and proclaimed that it was “like writing history with lightning.” Mark E. Benbow,
Giles,
Qtd. in Hunter v. Underwood, 471 U.S. 222, 229 (1985).
The standard history alleges that the point of the provision was to legalize and formalize black disenfranchisement that had heretofore been pursued in a more informal, ad hoc manner. S
That enlightened white sentiment in the North was untroubled by the decision is evident in the response of Harper's Weekly, which pointed to “new negro crime, by which is meant against white women, [which] is due to the notion of political and social equality implanted by the gift of suffrage.”
R. Volney Riser,
Pildes,
William M. Wiecek,
Saul Brenner,
D
“It is hostile to a democratic system to involve the judiciary in the politics of the people,” Frankfurter wrote, evidently considering it less hostile to permit gross legislative malapportionment. Colegrove v. Greene, 328 U.S. 549, 554 (1945).
Giles v. Teasley, 193 U.S. 146 (1904). Justice Day, “not unmindful of the gravity” of the issues raised, concluded that the Court had no right to review the state court's ruling.
Thurgood Marshall,
Nixon v. Condon, 286 U.S. 73 (1932); Grovey v. Townsend, 295 U.S. 45 (1935); Smith v. Allwright, 321 U.S. 649 (1944); Rice v. Elmore, 165 F. 2d 387 (C.C.A. 4th, 1947); Terry v. Adams, 345 U.S. 461 (1953).
14 Stat. 546.
William Wirt Howe,
Clyatt v. United States, 197 U.S. 207, 222 (1905).
Hodges v. United States, 203 U.S. 1, 17 (1906).
Bailey v. Alabama, 211 U.S. 452, 454 (1908).
Bailey v. Alabama, 219 U.S. 219, 244 (1911).
United States v. Reynolds, 235 U.S. 133, 146 (1914).
O
Clyatt v. United States, 197 U.S. 207, 223 (1905).
C
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
Ky. Acts 1904, §1.
Paul David Nelson,
Richard A. Heckman & Betty J. Hall,
The law was amended in 1950 to permit the admission of “qualified negroes.”
Gong Lum v. Rice, 275 U.S. 78, 81 (1927).
A
288 U.S. 71, 76.
18 Stat. 335.
109 U.S. 3, 13.
230 U.S. 126, 138 (1913).
R
235 U.S. 151, 161 (1914).
186 F. 966, 971 (8th Cir. 1911).
252 U.S. 399.
Letter from Holmes to Hughes, (N
196 U.S. 375, 378.
William J. Collins & Marianne H. Wanamaker,
The brief also referred to preserving “racial integrity,” and to “negroes carry[ing] a blight with them wherever they go.” Brief for Defendant in Error 11, 13 (1917).
245 U.S. 60, 80.
W
The opinion may be found at Josh Blackman's Blog, July 18, 2017.
U.S. D
Michael Jones Corea,
Title Guarantee v. Garrott, 42 Cal. App. 152, 183 (1919).
271 U.S. 323, 332.
E.g., United Cooperative Reality Co. v. Hawkins, 269 Ky. 563, 565 (1937); Ridgeway v. Cockburn, 296 N.Y. 936, 942 (1937); Meade v. Dennistone, 173 Md. 295, 302 (1938); Doherty v. Rice, 240 Wis. 389, 397 (1942); Lyons v. Waller, 191 Okla. 567, 569 (1942).
100 U.S. 303, 308. In Carter v. Texas, 177 U.S. 442, 449 (1900), the Court held that black defendants must be granted an opportunity to establish jury exclusion.
118 U.S. 356.
This case is thoroughly discussed in T
State v. Brownfield, 39 S.E. 2 (S.C. 1901).
Brownfield v. South Carolina, 189 U.S. 426, 428.
192 U.S. 226, 230.
188 U.S. 519, 520.
200 U.S. 316, 321 (1906).
212 U.S. 278, 281.
W. Lewis Burke,
218 U.S. 161, 167.
The Court adopted this rationale concerning employment discrimination. Griggs v. Duke Power Co., 401 U.S. 424 (1971).
194 U.S. 547, 548.
199 U.S. 547, 551.
203 U.S. 563, 574.
In dissent, Justice Peckham, while abhorring the lynching, found no evidence that the sheriff had been responsible. 214 U.S. 386, 426.
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
278 U.S. 63.
279 U.S. 737.
W
Hammer,
Lochner,
Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919).; Frohwerk v. United States, 249 U.S. 204 (1919); Debs v. United States, 249 U.S. 211 (1919).
Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 624 (1919); Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 672 (1925).
D
B
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
Thus, while Frankfurter was ever the Court politician seeking to influence the votes of his colleagues, Holmes maintained a courteous aloofness.
Wilson remarked that Holmes was “as free as was possible for men of their generation from common nineteenth century prejudices.”
C
Vegelahn v. Gunter, 167 Mass. 92, 107 (1896).
R
H
H
O
H
C
R
H
H
H
H
Benjamin Kaplan,
James Bradley Thayer,
E.g., Lochner,
H
Southern. Pac. Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 217 (1917).
E.g. Lochner,
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
Oliver Wendell Holmes es, Jr.,
Posner,
J
Paul Freund,
W
Charles Carpenter,
Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.,
A
H
I
S
L
H
Penn. Coal Co. v. Mahon, 250 U.S. 393 (1922).
Karl N. Llewellyn,
D
Benjamin N. Cardozo,
Brenda Wineapple,