Publicado en línea: 30 sept 2022
Páginas: 183 - 193
DOI: https://doi.org/10.25143/socr.23.2022.2.183-193
Palabras clave
© 2022 Jānis Musts, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
Deductivism or, as Luís Duarte d'Almeida calls it, rule-deductivism is a view that some parts of justification of a legal decision can be reconstructed by using legal syllogism (Duarte, 2019). Because of the prevalence of rule-deductivism (Alexy, 1989; MacCormick, 2005; Larenz & Canaris, 1995; Neimanis, 2004; Plotnieks, 2009) and in order not to get complacent, it is important to engage with critics who challenge the dominant view. This somewhat polemic is helpful and necessary to advance the understanding of the role (if any) that the legal syllogism has in justification of legal decisions.
This article aims to examine Luis Duarte d'Almeida's arguments against rule-deductivism in order to refine theoretical understanding of the role that legal syllogism has in justification of legal decisions.
In this article, three main research methods have been used: the descriptive, the deductive, and the analytical method. The descriptive and deductive methods are used to reconstruct Duarte's arguments against rule-deductivism, i.e., to elucidate and explicate the assumptions that are at the core of the critique. The analytical method is used to understand which theoretical assumptions are and are not essential to rule-deductivism.
In the first four chapters of the essay “
The first notion of rule-deductivism is the view that the legal syllogism is a model of the justification of law-applying judicial decisions. In this model, the premises of the legal syllogism entail that the judge “
Duarte notes that this conclusion does not justify that a judge
Duarte argues that the modified rule cannot be a reconstruction of the relevant statutory rule because rule-deductivists claim that the major premise is the section of the statute. In addition, the modified rule is not equivalent to, nor entailed by, the original formulation of the major premise; and the statute does not plausibly express the modified rule. (Duarte, 2019) Although Duarte does not mention this, such objections to the first notion of rule-deductivism are salient insofar as the legal system contains norms that are not already in the form of the modified major premise.
One can summarise Duarte's objections to the first notion of rule-deductivism in the following way. The notion that the legal syllogism is a model of the justification of law-applying judicial decisions is unattainable if:
the major premise is a section of the statute; there are instances when legal consequences of the statutory rule are formulated in such a way that they do not demand action from the judge (i.e., “judge ought to rule that”); the aforementioned statutory rules cannot be taken to demand such action.
Duarte initially describes the second notion of rule-deductivism as “
Duarte's critique of the second notion of rule-deductivism consists of two parts: an argument that the legal syllogism is inadequate and three rebuttals to potential counterarguments. Duarte argues that the legal syllogism is inadequate by showing that there exist cases where the court's argumentation cannot be reconstructed by using the legal syllogism. In one such case, the court used the general purpose (
The first counterargument to Duarte's criticism is concerned with the scope of rule-deductivism; one may say that such cases as described above are not in the class of cases that the legal syllogism is meant to model. Duarte disagrees because it is a case in which an existing law is applied to a particular case. Furthermore, the fact that courts and lawyers frequently construct such arguments is strong pre-theoretical evidence for the legitimacy of such arguments (Duarte, 2019).
The second objection consists of an assertion that the court used a different major premise that is not identical to the rule expressed by the text of the provision. Duarte dismisses this argument because he thinks that “
The third objection consists of an assertion that the court implicitly used a different minor premise. Duarte dismisses this objection by reminding that the court did not try to show that the facts of the case were an instantiation of the operative facts of some rule (Duarte, 2019).
Duarte's objections to the second notion of rule-deductivism can be summarised in the following way. The second notion of rule-deductivism is unattainable because there exist legitimate cases where it seems (pre-theoretically) that:
an existing legal rule is applied only by reference to its general purpose; no attempt is made to create a new legal rule that can be used as the major premise; no attempt is made to subsume the facts of the cases under the antecedent of some rule.
The first thing to note, Duarte's arguments are linked in the sense that the arguments against the second notion of rule-deductivism can be used to attack the first notion of rule-deductivism. This is because the argument against the former aims to show that there are cases that no form of legal syllogism can model. Therefore, if one wants to show that the first notion of rule-deductivism is tenable, one must refute both arguments. Because of this, it is prudent to start the examination of Duarte's argument by first addressing the more general critique, i.e., the arguments against the second notion of rule-deductivism.
Before addressing the main points of Duarte's argument, two assumptions must be dealt with. First, Duarte insists that, according to rule-deductivists, when the facts of the case cannot be subsumed under the operative facts of the statutory provision, a judge must construct a watertight description of the operative facts that any case must meet for the provision to be applicable (Duarte, 2019). Although it is a fair burden to place on the legislator who is tasked with creating a provision, it may be that it is an unreasonable burden to place on a judge when he is confronted with a gap in the law. In spite of Duarte's insistence on the contrary, rule-deductivism does not commit one to such a position. Consider the following example.
Using hand grenades to kill fish in lake Dzintars is clearly against the general purpose of the provision but the facts of the case only partially fall under the operative facts of the statutory rule. The question remains what options the judge has. In this case, there are three broad ways to approach the expansion of the antecedent of the statutory rule using teleological correction:
get rid of some operative facts that form a add operative facts that form a
If a judge thinks that, given the “If a person catches fish in lake Dzintars, then...” An example of a modification using the third option, i.e., replacing one of the operative facts with a different one: “If a person uses a fishing rod or any other method to catch fish in lake Dzintars, then…”
Although both (I) and (II) encompass the facts of the case, these two solutions have the risk of over-inclusiveness.
If one wants to avoid this risk completely or take the view that there are cases in which the judge does not commit himself to what the relevant characteristics of a case are that can be universalised to other relevantly similar cases (Duarte, 2019; Duarte & Michelon, 2017), then the second option offers an appropriate solution because of its versatility. The versatility comes from the fact that the disjunct that the judge can add to the rest of the antecedent can be formulated in many different levels of abstraction in respect to the facts of the case.
The first level of abstraction provides for the following:
creates a new universalizable rule that is more in line with the if the judge gives sufficient reasons that, given the reduces the chance of over-inclusiveness to the minimum.
In this example, one can create the first level of abstraction by omitting only the constants (i.e., the person who used the hand grenades) and the facts of the case that are already subsumed under the original parts of the antecedent of the statutory rule. This is the lowest level of abstraction possible. Furthermore, the first level of abstraction is unavoidable, if one wants to maintain that the decision is universalizable to relevantly similar cases.
In higher-level abstractions of the facts of the case, the judge can omit some or all irrelevant aspects of the case in respect to the general purpose of the provision, e.g., the type or material of the hand grenade. One can even abstract the term “hand grenades” to “explosive devices”. This shows that the scope of the major premise implicitly or explicitly created by the judge can be in different levels of adherence to the general purpose of the statutory rule. Rule-deductivists are not committed to the view that this adherence must be perfect.
When explaining what the integral and orthodox elements of rule-deductivism are, Duarte points out two essential things that concern the major premise, i.e., that it is a general legal rule and that it is hypothetical in form (Duarte, 2019). The aforementioned perfect adherence to the general purpose of the statutory rule is not one of these integral and orthodox elements. Therefore, the first assumption of what rule-deductivism demands, i.e., that when the facts of the case cannot be subsumed under the operative facts of the statutory provision a judge must construct
Secondly, Duarte insists that when the courts “
In order to refute Duarte's main argument against the second notion of rule-deductivism, one must show that the examples he provided are not properly characterised as cases were:
an existing legal rule is applied only by reference to its general purpose; no attempt is made to create a new legal rule that can be used as the major premise; no attempt is made to subsume the facts of the cases under the antecedent of some rule.
Duarte offers two cases that allegedly are of the same sort and cannot be modelled by the legal syllogism, i.e.,
It is clear that the court gave a new construction (“
Duarte's main example comes from the oldest of the two cases –
Duarte reconstructs the statutory rule and the facts of (2)
The second objection of the defendant was about the fact that Mary Taylor was not a
Such a reconstruction of the court's arguments cannot be simply dismissed because Duarte acknowledges that rule-deductivists do not think that the court must strictly follow the form of the legal syllogism, i.e., it is sufficient that the court's justification can be represented as an instance of the legal syllogism (Duarte, 2019; Leiter, 2010).
To summarise, in
The problem with Duarte's criticism of the first notion of rule-deductivism is that it is contingent upon several uncommon assumptions, i.e., the notion that the legal syllogism is a model of the justification of law-applying judicial decisions is unattainable if:
the major premise is a section of the statute; there are instances when legal consequences of the statutory rule are formulated in such a way that they do not demand action from the judge (i.e., “judge ought to rule that”); and the aforementioned statutory rules cannot be taken to demand such action.
It seems that Duarte's argument against the first notion of rule-deductivism is effective at showing that, given the three assumptions that are not essential to the first notion of rule-deductivism, it is unattainable. The strength of such an argument is contingent upon the acceptability of the assumptions among rule-deductivists.
If Duarte maintains that these three assumptions are essential to rule-deductivism, then there are fewer legal theorists who would subscribe to rule-deductivism than Duarte leads us to believe. For instance, Duarte claims that Neil MacCormick and Robert Alexy are prominent authors who have defended rule-deductivism (Duarte, 2019). It seems that Alexy would not endorse the third assumption, because he stressed that there can be several different formalisations of a statutory rule, e.g., “
Furthermore, it can be argued that MacCormick does not endorse the first notion of rule-deductivism and, because of that, it does not matter if he subscribes to any of the three assumptions. Duarte recognises that, when MacCormick is more careful, he explains that in order to complete the justification of the law-applying decision the legal syllogism must have an additional implicit premise, i.e., that the judge should apply the law when it is relevant and applicable (Duarte, 2019; MacCormick, 1978). Therefore, MacCormick's view of the legal syllogism (without the additional premise) is more in line with the second notion of rule-deductivism.
One can argue that it is important that the added premise is implicit, because of the purpose of justification. As such it would be an argument against the first notion of rule-deductivism and any other model of justification that aims to explicitly justify that the judge ought to apply a statutory rule (provision). When justifying a decision, a judge must adhere to two important functions of justification, i.e.:
to to
If justification is meant to inform and convince the parties to the case, the aim of the second notion of rule-deductivism is more in line with these functions because the conclusion is directed at said parties. In contrast, the conclusion of the first notion of rule-deductivism is directed at the judge, i.e., that the judge has an obligation to apply the instantiated legal consequences.
To summarise, Duarte's argument against the first notion of rule-deductivism is effective given some more or less exotic assumptions that are not essential to rule-deductivism. R. Alexy's description of the relevant parts of the internal justification shows that one can maintain that the legal syllogism is a model of the justification of law-applying judicial decisions and reject most of the assumptions that are essential for Duarte's critique to work. Although Duarte's arguments fail to show that the first notion of rule-deductivism is unattainable in all circumstances, the conclusion may be reached by considering that justification is mainly addressed to the parties to the case, not the judge.
A thorough reconstruction and examination of Duarte's arguments against rule-deductivism lead to several conclusions.
Firstly, Duarte's general critique of the legal syllogism as inadequate in properly representing even some parts of a justification of a law-applying decision where the judge expands the scope of a statutory rule, depends on a faulty assumption, i.e., that the scope of the major premise must always be in perfect adherence to the general purpose of the statutory rule. Absent to this assumption (that is not essential to rule-deductivism), legal syllogism is compatible with Duarte's assertion that there are cases where the judge expands the scope of the statutory rule but does not commit himself to what the relevant characteristics of the case are that can be universalized to other relevantly similar cases.
Secondly, Duarte's criticism of the first notion of rule-deductivism is effective, but only insofar as one also adheres to several contentious assumptions that are held by some rule-deductivists but are not essential to rule-deductivism. A more apt critique of the first notion of rule-deductivism may be levied by appealing to the purposes of justification.
Finally, an awareness that there exist such sets of assumptions that are not compatible with rule-deductivism is useful for further refinement of theoretical understanding of the legal syllogism.