Online veröffentlicht: 23. Dez. 2022
Seitenbereich: 119 - 139
DOI: https://doi.org/10.25143/socr.24.2022.3.119-139
Schlüsselwörter
© 2022 Kristaps Zariņš, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
As researchers of the field, such as Russell Sandberg, point out – to ignore and not be guided by the sophisticated analysis of theologians and their work over the centuries would be too “conceiting”; therefore, noteworthy is Weber's idea of tolerance, or tolerantly positive criticism, in regards of how he chooses to compare the three dimensions of relations – spiritual (religion), social (society) and legal environment. In particular, the study will focus, among other articles, on the following works of Weber:
Such a relatively new aspect as religious law and church law, similar to how it was once discovered and later used for social argumentation by Weber, helps to clarify some, mostly essential, questions of the canon law of European countries, which are considered from the angle of the history of law – naturally standing far from the topics discussed in theological works; due to the particularities of their origin and past, they clearly have a consistent legal nature and character. Moreover, depth of this field of law lies in the fact that it is a direct and still living heir of Latin law.
Study, as a sociological material of law, outlines the structure of the work and is the social understanding of the norms of canon law, which is reflected in the practical law, law that makes the different and common foundation and structure of the state law and canon law. Due to the limited space, not all studies of the field are mentioned, but only those works that are highlighted by Weber in his studies, specifically in the work
Works of various well known canon law authors are examined to identify particularities of canons and their place and role in other legal disciplines. It appears that the author does not want to bring forward thesis that the religious peculiarity is the one that dictates law or creates law, instead he tries to reflect the legal ideology arising from it, as well as the collision of material and spiritual values and interests created by it. No matter how deeply economically and politically conditioned social influence of law on religious ethics may be in some cases, its core features and texts can always be found in religious sources, their messages, promises and writings. (Weber, 1949)
Due to the Judaic laconism of Roman law, it is necessary to provide explanation that
Weber views the structure of religious law, or, as he puts it – the “entity”, as a systematic religious “typology”, and also places the burden of historical research on this discipline. Contrary to what Weber says about the importance of rank, class and economy in law, the author also talks about the social phenomenon of religious law as an object of canon law, by looking at it in conjunction with the idea of church law. However, when looking from the point of view of Weber's “typology”, or as Weber says, since recognition and coexistence of religion and law is necessary, these main ideas expressed by Weber are typological, as far as it is considered that these different types of ethical law are historically and typically significantly related to social reality and the great contrasts between the scope of church and state law.
The author does not intend to provide a completely justified description of the canon law under examination, and in terms of the scope of the work, the objective is not to delve into the details of Roman law, which in spite of being a very good work itself, is too voluminous but the history of Europe, which is formed by the “continent of nations”, in the creation of a unified national space has repeatedly failed: “
For better illustration, it is necessary to highlight those features of canon law, which are opposite or different from those of the law of the Roman peoples, by which modern civil legal process is understood, or which are different in a socio-atheistic state system, and, in addition, Weber pays great attention to their relationship with ethical norms mentioned in Christianity, such as sources of law, and their manifestations and influence in the culture of social jurisprudence. Weber says that a study of the sociology of religion, in which the main attention would not be devoted to these particularly important moments, perhaps by softening them, or by sometimes adding to them other, more categorical than possible aspects, would indicate that, of course, all the contradictions and realities of qualitative systematics can be perceived as purely quantitative differences in certain legal issues, but they cannot be softened by reflecting common and different features of law and religion, where a rule of law, an obedient servant of the law, speaks on behalf of both the state and the church. (Weber, 1949)
Reiterating this obviousness and duality of religion and law would not be fruitful. Therefore, in response to the call of the great sociologist, it is clearly necessary to mention the quintessence of the qualitative and quantitative analysis of legal research considering which of these prisms of legal values is more vital and which should be foremost highlighted more than the others and how to correctly compare them from a historical point of view with the insights expressed by social reality and values. The following conclusion deserves recognition and seems appropriate: “
The state, as an institution of law, and the connection between religion and the Christian doctrine of precondemnation, by its very nature excludes the possibility that the state could support religion by showing intolerance, as it happens in various aspects of human rights, where there is wide pluralism and man is the absolute embodiment of these rights. If the divine rights cultivated by the Christian faith, which in reality manifested as infallibility of the church, merge or completely disappear in front of man as a phenomenon of creation, and if it is presumed that man is absolute and unique, then his rights are also unquestionable and as absolute as the man himself. (Harold, 2010,
However, the church denies this idea, because it recognises only divine authority in everything, including laws, because they have emerged from God, for example, such sources as the Old Testament, the books of Moses, etc. The spirit of canon law and its substance clearly speak of it. Therefore, the state, when analysed from the point of view of the doctrine of Christian texts, cannot be “doomed” because it is itself a form of perfection and true embodiment of the social environment of the society, but the Christian society, or even a smaller entity of the state – a citizen of the state, from a perspective of the Christian scriptures, which anyway constitute the main sources of customary law, such as the 10 Commandments, is eternally sinful and condemned and therefore seeks forgiveness of eternal sin, even more so – not in this life, which would be absurd from the point of view of legal principles, because it would mean that the guilt of a person is presumed from birth, and also the guilt can be redeemed (compensated) only in a specific, truly sacred way – through a religious institute intended for forgiveness of sins. This guilt characterises any member of society despite the fact that there is no such form of presumption of guilt in law, it would be an abstract and utopian idea even for the most fanatical advocates of legal absolutism.
Thus, attention should be paid to the role of religion in the most legally important document of the state – the constitution, similarly as for the role of the church – to the source of its religion, the Bible. The only difference is that while the clauses established in the constitution do not directly and individually affect matters of faith, morality and conscience, judgments contained in the texts of the holy scriptures and values, such as in the Bible (Old Testament and New Testament), are the source of law and morality (condition of what is good, what is happiness and what is the right action). For example, in the context of comparative international constitutional law, this religious aspect is well established in the constitutions of different countries, including Latvia (see, for example, “
The origin and phenomenon of law may have begun with the emergence of social consciousness of society and usurpation of the power of some authority over it, but later resulted in strengthening of the individual's autonomous rights, in the absolute element and form of human rights. Nevertheless, as Weber points out, law perhaps has a dimension of Christian values which manifests itself in the form of divine verticality through the fact that the basic moral legitimation of law can be found in religious texts and its first and main cause is God (
Several other philosophers have already mentioned
Similarly comparable would be social and religious norms, where the former are secular and practical to the extent possible, as opposed to the objective rational values expressed in religious texts as a source of law. For example, Romans, when coming to conclusion that ethical elements can be found in every legal system, defined law as the art of good and just (
On the other hand, in the early Middle Ages, this fundamental idea, interpreted by theologian and scholastic Thomas Aquinas, transformed into a dimension of biblical values, creating ideal law in an ideal state that is under the authority of the church (similar to Plato's utopian state), but with the rise of humanist ideas and their spread in Western Europe, the same law became more specific and evolved into subjective (natural) human rights, even providing for respect for human dignity.
As Otfried Hoffe aptly points out in his work
In comparison, while Cicero writes in his work
In his views, Weber goes even further and considers that modern political technology is characterised by the fact that religion itself is also transformed and as a result the capitalistic “spirit” is formed, that is, through brutal dualism the main objective of the corpus of law is incorporated – to look at the
For example, Viennese doctor Johann Peter Frank in his 1779 essay
It is clear that the church and religion are generally ignored and its quintessence is lost, but it took several hundred years before some of the most prominent critics of the unity of church and state from the early Renaissance and decadence, Thomas Hobbes with his brutal ethics, and John Locke, by seeing the essence of happiness in the state affairs (law), could arrive to such a remarkable “forgetfulness” of church and religion in the field of state and law.
However, returning to the systematic aspect of the church, when looking at the socio-legal issues of religion and views based on human rights where everyone can be an atheist or a believer in regard to their personal beliefs, but in the common public legal space they all certainly meet some sort of religious ceremony, it must be concluded that the influence of religion is felt in traditions, as well in law, which is based on the values derived from them. This is especially evident in the culture of the Western Europe and in the deeply rooted traditions these nations, and in general everywhere where the beliefs of the Christian faith prevail.
A culture based on religious values and a culture based on human rights form their belief system. In the background of the traditions of the Christian worldview, purely religious holidays are widely accepted and celebrated in the form of positive norms – official holidays celebrate several thousand-year-old events that are purely religious in nature and have no connection with the secular world at all (birth of the prophet, resurrection); an official anthem of religious content is sung, which even contains an indication of how it is an official prayer (in the case of the National Athem of Latvia – the solemn prayer of the people, Law on the National Anthem of Latvia, Article 2). Thus solemn (symbolic) oaths are taken (e.g. on the Bible or on the constitution) and, finally, these religious texts and manifestos stemming from them are carefully enshrined at the constitutional level in an otherwise profane world, and as a result atheistic beliefs and traditions remain in the minority against such a background. Besides, the institution of the oath is a purely moral paradigm, an ethical standard for a certain action, it is not an ordinary material legal norm, since its origins are purely religious, symbolic and ceremonial.
The question arises what the sources of such a discipline of cultural law, a religious law are, seen as a form of expression of traditions, which cannot be measured the same as pure canon law, and how such wide recognition can be found, even among people completely unrelated to faith. Further question include what the basic source of the moral expression of these values is – whether those are Greek and Roman century-long philosophical reflections, or widely known unwritten moral views of natural rights, or religious texts in the reflections of law (similarly, as a reflection of ideas in Plato's allegory of the cave) which form the legal opinion and consensus of the last millennia basic source codes.
In response, Weber concluded that in contrast to the Roman school of law, in no other culture in the world, except in the West, where pragmatism is rooted from the time of Thucydides and its prehistory is used, there is nothing that would indicate a rational legal theory. In other earlier civilisations, in prehistory, there are no strict legal systems and forms of legal thinking that characterise Roman law and Western law, which is based on the former. Such a phenomenon as canon law is also known only in the West. (Vēbers, 2004)
Thus, for example, Roman law was deeply rooted in the Catholic lands of Southern Europe and later also in entire Western Europe. Rationalisation of private law, if it is interpreted as simplification of legal concepts and division of legal material, reached its highest development in the Roman law of late antiquity and, on the contrary, was the least developed in the countries that reached the highest degree of rationalisation, including England, where the renaissance of Roman law failed. (Franklin, [1736] 1904; Weber, 2004)
Weber quite well captures the “
Calvinists, on the other hand, saw a form of ideal norm in the law, which is impossible to achieve but must be constantly striven for (Journal of Law and Religion, 2006). Regarding Calvinism, the views expressed by Thomas Aquinas in his work
Explaining the statements of the Bible as “
Observance of such a principle “
Over time, it became impossible for the state to intervene in various matters, such as appointment and transfer of clerical positions, which, on the contrary, was described in detail by the norms of canon law. Thus, the leader of the English revolution, Oliver Cromwell, together with John Brown, constituted the church as a socio-legal unit (Landow, 2005), or even a phenomenon. He was an advocate for universal religious freedom, but his concept of “holy parliament” – the separation of church and state where they (the people of faith) were pietists for positive religious motives and represented influence of that, similarly as Roger Williams, guided by the same considerations, advocated unconditional, unrestricted religious toleration and separation of church and state, where the state has no resemblance to the church, contrary to what, from the point of view of public law, had been accepted since the early decadence of Roman law (Vēbers, 2004). For example, in the resolution of the English Baptists of Amsterdam (in 1612 or 1613), the demand for freedom of conscience as a defense of one's positive rights appeared for the first time from the state (Schluchter, 2017). It reads: “
During the Hellenistic era, in the Roman Empire, also in Islamic lands, religious tolerance prevailed for a long time, limited only by considerations of public order, which were based on laws, even if they were not always compatible with the texts of canon law. As, for example, Philipp Jakob Spener points out, it is about the fundamental rights of Christians, which were guaranteed by the apostles when they formed the first Christian congregations. Also, the Puritan opinion developed about the place of individual people in the church and about the legal sphere of their activity, which derives from
The Arminian erastic position of the idea of extending state sovereignty to church affairs was represented by the monopoly of autonomously created state sovereignty, which corresponds with the political interests of the law of that time, which were pragmatically but tendentiously rooted already in the church law culture of the Renaissance. In addition, an ardent follower of the idea of Arminianism, or prof. Jacob Arminius (
It is also known that Nietzsche's supporters, based on fundamentally similar reasons, have attributed a positive ethical meaning to the idea of eternal return, leaving the church in the background, compared to the formation of the state. Erasmus (1466–1536), a Dutch humanist who declared the dogmatic “
However, within the framework of an unbelieving state or under the influence of “
Of course, consistent implementation of principle “
Thus, the place that Protestant teaching intended to give to the “
However, the Puritan understanding of “legality” as a test of “
Christianity, which was originally the teaching of wandering artisans, in contrast to Judaism, in the early Middle Ages, and later under the influence of Puritanism, paid much attention to the fact that ethical norms should be replaced by Christian norms and that these in turn should be carefully collected (codified) and declared through written laws, such as laws of the church or even laws of the state. This approach with such interpretation of law often encountered a problem that a happy person in the sense of law is rarely satisfied with this fact of obtaining happiness itself. He also wants to be happy in the sense of law, and, moreover, by referring to the thesis that the law must ensure “happiness”, he wants to be sure that he deserves it – first of all, in comparison with others, he wants to believe that the less fortunate received it by merit and that happiness itself is “legitimate” and he aspires to be “legitimate” together with it (Vēbers, 2004).
The rational need for elements of the theodicy of suffering and death, such as death penalty as a legally enforceable form of punishment, was clearly expressed in law. In regard to this, any hierocratic church fights it with virtuosic religiosity and ethical dogmas, i.e., it, in the form of an institution, organises a community of “grace” of moral forgiveness, which has nothing to do with state laws. Theodicy (from Greek –
Weber says that the church, as a legitimate institution, seeks to replace the acts of state power with its own monopolised but supposedly democratic means of salvation. However, provided that it is a universal institution of “grace”, the Christian values preach is as recognised, and obedience to its authority is based on its religious texts and law derived from them and which has a direct connection with articles of faith included in religious texts. However, in the field of ideas of general law, the church remains solely and exclusively faithful to the legal order established by the state.
Weber states that from the sociological point of view of law, one can see a complete parallel with the struggle of bureaucracy against order, the political rights of the aristocracy, and the forms of state and church rule of law in the political sphere of law. “Rational”, as a belief in some important “canon”, was the highest artistic ideal of the Renaissance; rational, as a rejection of all traditional ties and belief in the power of
The nature of church disciplines and canon law through the religious nature of worldly asceticism, as Weber called it, linking it also to various elements, such as professional ethics and professional jurisprudence, brings along a problem that has been little studied until now, one of the reasons being because the effect of church discipline is not always spread uniformly. Therefore, the police control of the lives of the faithful in a way that borders along the lines of inquisition is realised in the domain of the state church. In a hierocratic union – in the church, the shepherds (pastors) of its congregations represent a certain “competence”, which is determined by the regulations. Church leadership or pontificate is, in its true sense, the same as the service established since the pontificate of Innocent III, where the separation of the position of
Namely, Weber compares a clergyman and its “competence” with an official, who is also a representative of power, yet only secular. Neither exercises this power as their own rights but always on behalf of an impersonal “institution”, in the interests of people's coexistence subject to some normatively formulated regulations, regardless of whether they are determined or not, but ascertained according to criteria corresponding to the regulations. A clergyman, who is subordinate to the hierarchy of “superiors” in clarifying and identifying legal issues, turns to the church administration “by instances”. Thus, religious communities (including church) belong to a union of dominion, an hierocratic association, i.e., whose power is based on giving or refusing grace. It answers the question: “
Even more, it is the process of traditionalism and long-term domination or ruling based on a charismatic leader and an organisation followed by the community, its disciples and followers who would firstly become officials and only then priests (Weber, 1949). The church, as a unique institution, which is just as relevant to its local regulations of social life and their subordination to internal canon norms, as opposed to a bureaucratic apparatus of state power, which does not consist in any part of canon norms, is a proof that the modern Western “state”, with the triumph of formalistic legal rationalism in it, as well as the emergence of the Western Church, was in large part work of lawyers, the main, though not the only, form of which was
Among the representatives of this domination structure are state officials, its pastors and laymen. In addition, submission takes place for legitimacy of one's rights, an impersonal
In legislation of Western countries, when viewed in the context of the church, the end result tends to the ratio of coercive force with which legal ruling or domination can be exercised through legislation, and it is not based on ethical “rights”, even if their objective criteria could be clarified, but on the “state”, which has a monopoly on “legitimate violence”. For example, in the Sermon on the Mount: “(..)
Because the entire process of the internal political functions of the state apparatus in the field of law and administration is ultimately regulated pragmatically, based on objective state considerations, with an absolute end in itself, that is, law serves the existence of the state which is a completely meaningless position in religion because canon norms do not require preserving or transforming the internal or external division of power but determine only traditions established from religious sources in the law.
According to Weber, this sinful empirical system can be contrasted with absolutely divine “
Law, which is in general related to existence of a coercive group (legal coercion) that influences the regulations of a system so that they are implemented in society, may be relevant because coercive means themselves are relevant. Virtue has a voluntary character, where no one demands its observance, in contrast to law, where there is a certain sanctioned, legitimate and significant all-encompassing character. As Weber points out, between “virtue” and “law” there are many higher acts of religiosity that are incomprehensible to those for whom they do not exist as values, just as incomprehensible, for example, the teaching of human rights is to those who reject this teaching altogether. (Edward, 1949)
To understand social action (
On the one hand, canon law could be labelled as
However, as Weber points out, not all legally guaranteed systems, including conventional norms, claim ethical character, and legal norms, which in some cases are purely goal-oriented in nature, claim it even less than religious and conventional norms. Moreover, the church exercises moral coercion to guarantee the moral norms of religious ethics. (Weber, 2004)
Therefore, law can be hierocratic and guaranteed by the authority – the head of the church, while the statutes of the community association, i.e. canonic norms, are subject to both value-rational traditions and religious texts, which at the same time serve as a source of law for them, just as they serve as a regulation of secular administration. Canon norms, among other norms, are not more significant from the point of view of respect for traditions, nor are they more universal than other norms, perhaps due to their religious nature which are based on prophetically sanctioned and sacred customs.
As Weber writes: “
The question of how the church acquires these monopoly claims, if they can be called as such at all in the domain of domination or ruling, is unclear because the church, as an institution to which, as Weber points out, membership is acquired “by birth”, while the circumstance of “institution” separates it from other associations of power, according to its position and status, there is a hierocratic domination of the domain and it has a paroxysmal territorial division, so that a specific hologram of introverted power would be more than understandable and legally correct in its many angles of application of canon law norms. (Vēbers, 2004)
It is precisely the observance of canon law which means that it is law founded on distinction or custom, for example, also on stricter forms of regulation, as well as observance of religious customs (Hiršs, 2008), and the assumption of autocephaly established within it suggests a certain legal succession which is referred to in spiritual texts and, above all, in the holy writings, or the Bible, similar to how it is summarised in the collection of dogmatic, religious, ethical and legal principles of Judaism, or the Talmud (Georg, 1889). The autocephalous aspect of the habits and customs of this principle (from ancient Greek
Therefore, this characteristic is the governing circumstance of the church's autonomy, organisational and office independence (for example, regarding bishops), and they are not subject to any higher church official, since they form the sanctioned law
To escape from the state of domination and come to true “humility”, which will eliminate this turmoil, the way of thinking itself and approach to it must be transformed, which is said to be done by creating a special kind of domination, types of power, namely pastoral power. Pastoral power means training in the execution of the orders of superiors, while submission and humility must become a human virtue
Weber devotes his reflections as much to views based on ancient culture, as well as to contrasts between law and religion, and searches for the causes of their conflict and forms of radical manifestations, as only this can identify and clarify the influence of typical and consistent religious norms of the church in the domain of law. Therefore, in Weber's works, certain parallels can be drawn with the collapse of the golden age of philosophy, the invasion of barbarians and the spread of Christianity, and thus, church dogmatics. He draws great attention to culture, spirit of capitalism, social environment and their typology, as well as tries to form an opinion on the seemingly incompatible or, on the contrary, model of inseparable church-state relations. Weber highlights an idea that the slave of the ancient world and the thinking of the modern social proletarian can understand each other as little as a European can understand a Chinese. Nevertheless, Weber admits that these capitalist relations cannot be viewed separately from other social vicissitudes and must be seen in the context of cultural phenomena, in this case together with the rules of church law, in their sense of canon law.
Weber links the church doctrine of canon law with the state, and politics with church. Law is viewed as an “objective force” driven by the spirit of the age, church dogmas, as religious pathos, are seen in acts sanctioned by state power, in their legitimacy. Following this, it can be found that there is no alternative to legal thinking in sociological sense. Whether we think as clerics, laymen or lawyers, it does not matter how but the legal regulation of the specified content is either significant or not, from which the legal relationship either exists or does not exist. Likewise, Roman (code) and Greek (philosophy) way of thinking is close to the lexicon of Christianity, only the form of their expression and understanding is different.
It is understood to be common for this religious-legal consciousness because it is the prophetic component of God's recognition that also forces us to recognise the ethically rational side of action, that is, domination from both the state and the church. Therefore, this highly important component of legal legitimacy can be guaranteed only internally – religiously with the hope of blessing and salvation of faith to preserve the legal order in question. In contrast, the religious component which is purely and practically maintained by the church, guarantees both internal and external order. Weber concludes that this order is quite close to law because it internally guarantees the pressure (moral or physical) exerted by a special state, unlike the church, as an apparatus whose direct functions include safeguarding of order and prevention of violations by force, but they always are and remain as
Simultaneously, in the
Weber's sociology of religion interweaves with sociology of domination, which is confirmed through the idea expressed by Weber and often mentioned by those who study Weber's works on the conjuncture of the power economy and are interested in the religious and legal foundations of world asceticism as “political theology”: “
When analysing the institutional church, Weber describes the structure of canon law as a “shading” of sociology of religion. According to this approach, modern state is something like the papal curia which can better prevent various conflicts with the help of priestly lordships or domination. This means that the church is an administration that is characterised by the following features which, in addition, coincide with the features of the state:
differentiated administration rank, as an institutional and legal structure; rationalisation of cult and dogma, as a form of application of the norm; claim and universal domination, as claims of atheists about general law; creation of a rational system and successive rule, as a set of human rights elements; relationship of loyalty between those who serve and those who rule, as a sovereign who serves the social consensus of power and religion.