Uneingeschränkter Zugang

Why Tracking Theories Should Allow for Clean Cases of Reliable Misrepresentation


Zitieren

Artiga, Marc. 2013. Reliable misrepresentation and teleosemantics. Disputatio V(37): 265-281.10.2478/disp-2013-0020Search in Google Scholar

Bourget, David and Mendelovici, Angela. 2014. Tracking representationalism. In Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers, ed. by Andrew Bailey. London: Continuum: 209-235.Search in Google Scholar

Burge, Tyler. 1988. Individualism and self-knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy 85: 649-663.10.5840/jphil1988851112Search in Google Scholar

Fodor, Jerry. A. 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Fodor, Jerry. A. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/5684.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Kriegel, Uriah. 2011. The Sources of Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199742974.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Martínez, Manolo. 2013. Teleosemantics and productivity. Philosophical Psychology 26(1): 47-68.10.1080/09515089.2011.625115Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. 2010. Mental Representation and Closely Conflated Topics. PhD thesis, Princeton University.Search in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. 2013a. Intentionalism about moods. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2(1): 126-136.10.1002/tht3.81Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. 2013b. Reliable misrepresentation and tracking theories of mental representation. Philosophical Studies 165(2): 421-443.10.1007/s11098-012-9966-8Search in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. 2014. Pure intentionalism about moods and emotions. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind, ed. by Uriah Kriegel, New York: Routledge: 135-157.10.4324/9780203116623-6Search in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. (Forthcoming). Propositionalism without propositions, objectualism without objects, properties, and kinds. In Non-Propositional Intentionality, ed. by Alex Grzankowski and Michelle Montague, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela. (MS). Phenomenal intentionality: How to get intentionality from phenomenal consciousness.Search in Google Scholar

Mendelovici, Angela, and Bourget, David. 2014. Naturalizing intentionality: tracking theories versus phenomenal intentionality theories. Philosophy Compass 9(5): 325-337.10.1111/phc3.12123Search in Google Scholar

Millikan, Ruth. G. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/4124.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Millikan, Ruth. G. 1989. Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy 86: 281-297.10.2307/2027123Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Millikan, Ruth. G. 2000. On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay About Substance Concepts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511613296Search in Google Scholar

Papineau, David. 1987. Reality and Representation. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Search in Google Scholar

Pietroski, Paul. M. 1992. Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73: 267-282.10.1111/j.1468-0114.1992.tb00339.xSearch in Google Scholar

Prinz, Jesse. 2002. Furnishing the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Bradford.10.7551/mitpress/3169.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Rupert, Robert. D. 1999. Mental representations and Millikan’s theory of intentional content: does biology chase causality? Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1):113-140.10.1111/j.2041-6962.1999.tb00860.xOpen DOISearch in Google Scholar

Shea, Nicholas. 2002. Getting clear about equivocal concepts. Disputatio 13: 34-47.10.2478/disp-2002-0010Search in Google Scholar

Shea, Nicholas. 2004. On Millikan. Belmont: Wadsworth.Search in Google Scholar

Sterelny, Kim. 1989. Fodor’s nativism. Philosophical Studies 55(February): 119-41.10.1007/BF00354184Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

eISSN:
0873-626X
Sprachen:
Englisch, Portuguese
Zeitrahmen der Veröffentlichung:
4 Hefte pro Jahr
Fachgebiete der Zeitschrift:
Philosophie, Einzelne philosophische Strömungen, Analytische Philosophie