Artikel-Kategorie: Original study
Online veröffentlicht: 08. März 2025
Seitenbereich: 7 - 11
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/biocosmos-2025-0003
Schlüsselwörter
© 2025 Edward Feser, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
According to a neglected line of argument, natural selection cannot account for reproduction. The argument is of interest not only for the challenge it poses to the sufficiency of Darwinian explanations, but also for its possible relevance to the definition of life, at least if that definition includes a reference to reproduction. In particular, an implication of the argument is that it may be impossible to define life in non-teleological terms or to explain it in terms of natural selection. The section that follows provides an exposition of the argument. In the section after that, I will address its relevance to biological teleology, and in the final section its relevance to defining and explaining life.
A brief formulation of the argument, and perhaps the earliest formulation, is given by Peter Geach in his book The reproductive mechanisms certainly cannot be explained just by saying that creatures which failed to develop them failed to reproduce their kind and perished: without these mechanisms there would be no raw material for any cause of evolution to work upon. So in this case there can be no story of natural selection to replace the ostensible teleological account.
(1)
As Geach explained, he is not criticizing evolutionary explanations in general and he is not making a point about sex organs in particular. (2) He is talking about reproduction in general, and arguing that an appeal to natural selection, in particular, cannot replace a teleological account of reproduction.
The basic idea of Geach’s argument is simple. It is commonly held that to explain a trait by way of natural selection is to obviate any basis for an irreducibly teleological account of it. For example, suppose we say that hearts first arose by way of a random mutation, that they pumped blood in those organisms which had them, that because they did so those organisms tended to survive and reproduce in greater numbers than those who lacked hearts, and that this in turn resulted in all their current descendants having hearts. This will be an explanation of the heart that makes reference only to what Aristotelians call efficient causes, without any need for final causes or teleology. Even if we still spoke of the heart as having the function of pumping blood, it is often claimed that such a description can be analyzed in terms of this causal story, so that it has no
Geach’s claim is that whatever we think of this approach to understanding other traits, it won’t work in the case of reproduction. For explaining a trait’s existence within a population by appeal to natural selection involves proposing a scenario in which certain ancestors of that population survived
Again, Geach’s point is not to deny the evolutionary thesis that new species descended from previously existing species. (3) His point is that natural selection in particular cannot account for reproduction in particular, and thus does not obviate the need for a teleological conception of reproduction. (Geach also suggests that this ought to make us less confident that we should eschew irreducibly teleological explanations of other traits, but I put that issue aside for present purposes).
John Haldane and J. J. C. Smart debated a longer version of the argument in their book
In reply, Smart suggests that while the emergence of proto-replicators is improbable, it could occur given enough time, and that current scientific speculation about them makes no reference to anything like the ‘channels’ of information transfer spoken of by Haldane.
(7) But this misses Haldane’s point. Replication involves more than just one thing bringing about another. Again, it involves the cause’s transmitting to the effect features that are
In general, argues Haldane, attempts to explain replication by reference to natural selection are going to entertain scenarios in which more complex forms of replication might arise from less complex forms, and then suppose that this approach might be extended to account for how replication could arise from non-replication. But this is fallacious, because whereas the difference between more and less complex replicators is one of degree, the difference between replicators and non-replicators is a difference in kind. (9) Adding sides to a polygon will in principle never yield a circle, even if it yields something that looks superficially like a circle. And if Haldane is right, adding complexity to non-replicating systems will in principle never yield replication, even if it were to yield something with the superficial appearance of replication.
A third and yet more detailed statement of the argument is developed by biologist Stephen Rothman in his book As new cells are produced, the progenitor or parent cell is
Rothman offers several further illustrations of the thesis that reproduction confers no survival advantage.
(12) In many species, one or both parents are absent when fertilization occurs, and a process cannot confer an advantage on an organism that is not present when it occurs. In some insects, the male does not survive the sexual act. The female mammal is put at a disadvantage by having to bear and give birth to offspring. Though offspring can, once mature, contribute to the survival of their parents, this is not usually true, and where it is true it is true only up to a point. For offspring are also new competitors for scarce resources. Some will suggest that reproduction confers an advantage to
Common to the arguments developed by Geach, Haldane, and Rothman are the theses that natural selection cannot explain reproduction insofar as it presupposes reproduction, and that this entails an unreduced teleological component in Darwinian explanation. This amounts to a ‘paradox’, as Rothman puts it, insofar as the whole point of the idea of natural selection, at least as it is commonly understood, is to open the way to a non-teleological explanation of all biological phenomena. (14) Geach, Haldane, and Rothman are also all agreed that this does not entail rejecting an evolutionary account of the origin of species. It entails only that there must be more to evolution than natural selection, and that teleology is among these additional ingredients.
Following Rothman, we might label the core thesis he shares in common with Geach and Haldane the ‘paradox of evolution’. It is important to note that not every claim these writers make in the course of setting out this paradox is essential to it. For example, some readers will no doubt resist Rothman’s claim that offspring afford no net survival advantage to parents. As Stephen Jay Gould might say, there is bound to be some speculative ‘just-so story’ that might seem to support the contrary thesis.
(15) Yet any such story will presuppose that reproduction of
It might be objected that even if natural selection cannot account for reproduction, it doesn’t follow that there couldn’t be some other process, distinct from natural selection, by which reproduction evolved. That is true, but it misses the point. As I’ve said, the writers I’ve been discussing aren’t denying that evolution occurred, and they aren’t even necessarily denying that reproduction came about by evolution. What they are denying is that
Note that, contrary to the impression usually given by the public controversy over Darwinism, it doesn’t necessarily follow that the teleology in question would entail theism or some other form of ‘intelligent design’. As André Ariew and other contemporary philosophers of biology have emphasized, two importantly different conceptions of teleology have been developed in the history of philosophy. (16) What Ariew calls the ‘Platonic’ conception takes the teleological features of a natural phenomenon to be extrinsic to it, deriving from the intentions of a designing mind. What he calls the ‘Aristotelian’ conception takes such features to be intrinsic to a natural phenomenon, a consequence of its nature. For the Platonic teleologist, the acorn aims toward becoming an oak only insofar as a designer put acorns together with that end in mind. For the Aristotelian teleologist, the acorn aims toward becoming an oak because that is simply part of what it is to have the nature of an acorn.
One could accept Geach’s, Haldane’s, and Rothman’s ‘paradox of evolution’ argument and give it either a Platonic or Aristotelian interpretation. Which one to opt for is a separate issue. The point of the argument itself is simply that the notion of natural selection fails to obviate the need for a teleological conception of
Perhaps it is obvious why currently popular attempts to naturalize the teleological notion of
But the standard objection to causal role theories is that a part of a system may have more effects than it has functions. For example, the heart also makes a thumping sound, but making a thumping sound is not plausibly one of its functions. Hence there must be more to function than causal role. This additional element is often said to be identified by etiological theories, which factor in also the historical origins of a part of a system. For example, on Ruth Millikan’s account, an organism’s heart has the function of pumping blood insofar as the fact that its ancestors’ hearts pumped blood caused them to survive and reproduce.
(18) But now the problem should be obvious. Millikan’s etiological analysis
Several proposed definitions of life, and it seems all the main alternative definitions, either directly or indirectly make reproduction essential to life. On Aristotle’s classic account, argues Gareth Matthews, a living thing is essentially a species-preserving thing, and ‘among
It is worth noting too that the favored ways of conceiving of
Biology after Darwin thus not only preserves the traditional Aristotelian view that reproduction is one of the fundamental properties of life, but if anything puts greater emphasis on reproduction. In
Now, this notion of self-perfection is teleological in nature, which makes it unattractive to post-Darwinian biologists keen to banish teleology. This aim of banishing teleology is also the motivation for the attempt to explain as much as possible by way of natural selection, which is thought to be the non-teleological mode of explanation
Their ‘paradox of evolution’ argument thus has the following implications for the nature of life, if reproduction is indeed partly definitive of life. First, if reproduction is essential to life and natural selection cannot explain the origin of reproduction, then natural selection cannot explain the origin of life. Second, if reproduction is essential to life and reproduction is irreducibly teleological in character, then life is irreducibly teleological in character.
This does not by itself strictly entail that reproduction and life are in fact irreducibly teleological, at least if there turns out to be some means other than appeal to natural selection to banish teleology from biology. But in the absence of some such alternative, it does put the biological anti-teleologist back to square one. Nor, as I have said, do these results by themselves entail that life cannot be given an evolutionary explanation of
Geach P.
He notes this in reply to a critic in Peter Geach and Gilbert Fulmer. “An Exchange between Peter Geach and Gilbert Fulmer,”
Geach.
Smart JJC, Haldane JJ.
Ibid., p.92.
Ibid., pp.92–93.
Ibid., p.152.
Ibid., pp.178–79.
Ibid., pp.93–96 and 179.
Rothman S.
Ibid., p.62.
Ibid., pp.79–80.
Ibid., pp.64–66 and 163–64.
Though it seems Darwin himself did not think natural selection entirely banished teleology. See Lennox JG. Darwin was a Teleologist.
Gould SJ. Return of the hopeful monster. In:
Ariew A. Platonic and Aristotelian roots of teleological arguments. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M. (eds.).
Cummins R. Functional analysis. In: Buller D. (ed.).
Millikan RG. Proper functions. In: Buller.
Matthews GB. Aristotle on life. In: Boden MA. (ed.).
Dawkins R. Chapter 2:
Bedau MA. The nature of life. In: Boden.
Smith JM.
In
For a recent exposition and defense, see Oderberg DS. The great unifier: form and the unity of the organism. In: Simpson WMR, Koons RC, Teh NJ. (eds.)
Fodor J, Piattelli-Palmarini M.
Nagel T.