Published Online: Sep 30, 2023
Page range: 199 - 236
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/bjals-2023-0008
Keywords
© 2024 Thomas Halper, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
“Nothing will come of nothing,” roars Lear. (1) His daughter, Cordelia, has refused to compete with her sisters in declaiming her love for her father. She has nothing to say, and so she gets nothing from him. It all seems obvious to Lear, seductively so. Only later does he understand that it is the other sisters who offered him nothing, empty praise that disguised their disdain, and that only Cordelia offered him something, genuine love. By then, of course, it is much too late. Nothing/something. The apparent simplicity of the distinction so easily misleads us. Nothing—literally, no thing—cannot be true. Even when Genesis 1:1 describes the Earth as formless and empty, it offers us a statement about something that is itself something.
Nothing/something. Courts begin someplace. Decisions do not arise
In this context, consider fundamental rights, which obligate the state to respect our liberty, for example, to let us speak or worship or not to speak or worship more or less as we choose. If the state wishes to infringe on these rights, it must scale the high hurdle of strict scrutiny, demonstrating that its goal is compelling and its means are narrowly tailored—all to minimize the intrusion into our fundamental rights. When the fundamental rights are expressed in the Constitution—like the right to speak or worship—there at least is an agreed upon place to begin, the text. But suppose the rights are not enumerated? The question as to how courts determine what qualifies as fundamental rights, then, is not merely an intellectual curiosity, but rather has profound practical consequences. How ought courts to determine whether the Constitution guarantees fundamental rights it does not express—when the Constitution itself contains no term called “fundamental rights” and no instructions as to how it should be interpreted?
Are there unenumerated fundamental rights? The most obvious answer is that the absence of evidence is evidence of absence. In short, if the right is not expressed, it does not exist. Supporting this is the commonsense observation that rights, particularly, fundamental rights, are clearly so important that their absence could hardly be dismissed as irrelevant or unimportant. Were the Framers too busy—perhaps, sharpening their quill pens or powdering their wigs—and so simply forgot to include them? But if some fundamental rights may go unexpressed, what is the point of the Constitution's expressing other rights? To the uninitiated, the whole matter of unenumerated rights seems to confuse nothing with something, asking whether rights can be there, when they are not there. It all conjures up the skills of a magician, who in our enlightened age we call an illusionist. Are the courts, defying Lear, conjuring up something out of nothing? Where is the authority that grants them this power?
On the other hand, in ordinary speech there is much that is understood though unexpressed. When I ask you to dinner, it is understood that I will not offer you a bowl of Fruit Loops and a cup of day-old coffee; it is also understood that you will not dress like big Bird and spend the evening yodeling. The understandings may be based on experience with me or with societal conventions, but that meanings may be unexpressed is universally regarded as a fact of life. Which is not to deny that the unexpressed nature may be a source of conflict and confusion. Ever since 1897, (2) the Supreme Court has been reading “liberty” in the Fourteenth Amendment's due process clause to include various provisions of the Bill of Rights that, though targeting the national government, (3) also apply to the states. Thus, as a practical matter, nearly everyone concedes that there are unenumerated fundamental rights in the Constitution. How, then, to determine what they are? Joe Biden, when chair of the Senate Judiciary Committee, thought the problem was more apparent than real. Is there a constitutional right to privacy? Go to a shopping mall and ask the first three or four people you see. “’Of course!’” they would answer. “And when I asked why [they] all said, ‘The Constitution.’” (4) QED. Though the method promises quick and decisive answers, for some reason it has not caught on.
An obvious alternative is the “forgotten Ninth Amendment,”
(5) which, to counter
This connection became the centerpiece of arguments set down by the Ninth Amendment's most prominent legal advocate, the distinguished Yale law professor, Charles L. Black, Jr. For him, the Declaration of Independence, “a juristic act [that] demolish[ed] one legal authority and set up another,” (9) had as much legal standing as the Constitution; indeed, the purpose of the Constitution and the Bill of Rights, in particular, was to implement the principles of the Declaration. A key potential means to achieve this implementation, he believed, was the open-ended Ninth Amendment, “a fountain of law,” (10) which he thought imposed an affirmative duty on both the national government and the states, as the rights are “retained by the people.” (11) He acknowledged that identifying the rights will be “a pack of troubles,” (12) but refusing to try conflicts with the command of the Amendment and must be rejected; “[t]he Ninth Amendment seems to be guarding something.” (13)
When the Amendment refers to rights, Black reasoned, it must mean the rights recognized around that time, (14) in other words, the rights declared in the Declaration, including the pursuit of happiness. As the meaning of this right has evolved, Black inferred that “The possession of a decent material basis for life is an indispensable condition ... to the pursuit of happiness;” (15) the result is a constitutional guarantee of a moderate standard of living plus a ban on every kind of discrimination, whether race, gender, or sexual orientation. (16) In Black's eyes, then, the Declaration via the Ninth Amendment granted enormous power to the national government to shape society for the better. The need for this, he believed was obvious, as he considered the Bill of Rights, by itself, “very plainly insufficient to found a system broad and comprehensive enough for a really free people.” (17)
It is not clear that Black's history is correct. For well over a century, many influential historians have argued that the point of the Constitution was not to make the Declaration's principles real, but instead to frustrate them. (18) If the Constitution was meant to enshrine the Declaration's rights, how to explain the Framers’ “never seriously considering adopting a bill of rights,” (19) twice voting it down at the constitutional convention; (20) and how to explain Madison's proposing the amendments in 1791 not to actualize the principles of the Declaration, but rather to deflate calls for a new constitutional convention made by leaders of the opposition Anti-Federalists? (21) The broad positive social welfare rights that Black found implicit in the Ninth Amendment, moreover, were clearly foreign to the Framers, who took for granted a system of quite limited government. Black also seemed indifferent to the very substantial cost of these rights, a cost that would deprive taxpayers of money that would otherwise enhance their freedom. Nor did he seem interested in the germane distinction between rights and interests. (22) Finally, laying all these criticisms aside, the guidance provided by the Declaration is so vague that it is barely guidance at all.
Accordingly, Justice Scalia examining the text, argued that the Ninth Amendment's “refusal to ‘deny or disparage’ other rights was far removed from affirming any one of them, and even further removed from authorizing judges to identify what they might be, and to enforce the judges’ list against laws duly enacted by the people.” (23) As he saw it, the potential of the Ninth Amendment was vastly overblown. Similarly, Russell Caplan, in a careful history, concluded that the Amendment “is not a cornucopia of undefined federal rights,” but was merely directed at “the maintenance of rights guaranteed by the laws of the states.” (24) No wonder Justice Jackson found its meaning “a mystery to me,” (25) and John Hart Ely derided it as “that old constitutional jester.” (26)
Given the extreme disagreements on such basic considerations, it is hardly surprising that the Ninth Amendment has not served to justify a major doctrine. When “in perhaps [its] most famous invocation,”
(27) Justice Goldberg mentioned it in a concurrence to
If the Ninth Amendment has not proved to be a vehicle for unenumerated fundamental rights, what options exist? The current uproar over
Incorporation is the process by which the Supreme Court has taken portions of the Bill of Rights, which originally applied only to the national government, (34) and applied them to the states. The mechanism used is the liberty dimension of the Fourteenth Amendment's due process clause. (35) Though the rights are expressed in the Constitution and in this sense are enumerated, their application to the states is not expressed, thus justifying the label “unenumerated.” For relying on “liberty” does not solve the problem, but merely changes it to: what rules guide the Court in its determination as to what liberty encompasses?
The first incorporation case was
In
In light of these seven early incorporation cases, what justifications are offered for applying rights to the states? Sometimes, the answer is none (
Granted that it might be good public policy to apply the Bill of Rights to the states, why should courts be the vehicle to accomplish this purpose?
While the Court was addressing incorporation, it was also deciding other cases bearing on unenumerated rights, perhaps, most famously,
This is not an unlimited right, but here the burden falls on New York to demonstrate that its abridgement of the right—denying employer and employee the opportunity to determine the conditions of employment—can be justified. Are bakers, unlike other workers, incapable of looking out for themselves? (50) Is their work “especially unhealthy”? (51) Is there some public benefit, perhaps more “clean and wholesome” bread, the law will produce? (52) Answering no to these questions, Peckham found the law contrary to the unenumerated right of liberty of contract and thus unconstitutional. (53) Throughout, he emphasized that “This is not a question of substituting the judgment of the Court for that of the legislature.” (54)
Justice Holmes, in his brief and famous dissent, surely gets the better of the argument. Peckham's logic may be fine, but as Holmes’ observed a quarter of a century before, “The life of the law has not been logic; it has been experience.” (55) Holmes, of course, is not pleading that law should be illogical. Instead, he is insisting that law arises as a function of human experience, in the sense that it represents political resolutions of social conflicts and not deductions from abstract principles; the Constitution rests on this common sense observation, and as it was made “for people of fundamentally differing views,” (56) it “is not intended to embody a particular economic theory, whether of paternalism ... or of laissez faire” that Peckham evidently cherished. (57)
How, then, can Peckham justify this right, liberty of contract, that is not expressed in the Constitution? Holmes, an exponent of judicial self-restraint, declares that he cannot. The “word liberty in the Fourteenth Amendment is perverted when it is held to prevent the natural outcome of a dominant opinion, unless it can be said that a rational and fair man necessarily would admit that the statute proposed would infringe fundamental principles as they have been understood by the traditions of our people and our law.” (58) The alternative would be unauthorized judicial legislation justified only by the judges’ ideology or policy preferences, neither of which had a basis in the Constitution. Peckham's claim that the Court had not usurped the legislature's policy making function was mere self-delusion. In contrast to his abstract argument, Holmes invoked history/tradition as a test to determine the constitutionality of an unenumerated right. Liberty of contract failed the test.
The magic key that Peckham imagined he had found that unlocked liberty of contract was what Justice Thomas recently dismissed as an “oxymoron that lack[s] any basis in the Constitution,”
(59) substantive due process. The Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments provide,
At least, that is what it means today. An exhaustive study of the original public meaning of due process in the Fifth Amendment, however, suggests a much narrower meaning of the term. Specifically, that “process” simply refers to “a formal document that provides a person notice of legal obligation,” for example, “a criminal defendant may not be deprived of life or liberty without first either person service of process or some legally valid alternative.” The clause, the authors believe, does not even “require that procedures be fair.”
(60) On the other hand, the nineteenth century saw a few cases positing substantive due process under the Fifth Amendment as applicable to the national government, in one, for example, calling due process “a restraint on the legislative as well as the executive and judicial powers of the government.”
(61) The infamous
In
Justice McReynolds, speaking for a seven-to-two Supreme Court majority, held that the statute exceeded “the limitations upon the power of the state and conflict[ed] with rights assured to [Meyer].”
(65) He conceded that the “desire of the legislature to foster a homogeneous people with American ideals ... is easy to appreciate,” but thought that the mere “knowledge of the German language cannot reasonably be regarded as harmful.”
(66) The law could “interfere with the calling of modern language teachers, with the opportunities of pupils to acquire knowledge, and with the power of parents to control the education of their own.”
(67) McReynolds, echoing Peckham in
McReynolds then returned to the controversy before him. “The American people,” he wrote, “have always regarded education and the acquisition of knowledge as matters of supreme importance which should be diligently promoted,” referencing the Ordinance of 1787.
(69) Like Holmes in
McReynolds is not usually held in high regard today. Holmes thought him “a savage,”
(70) Brandeis called him “an infantile moron,”
(71) and Taft said he was “fuller of prejudice than any man I have ever known.”
(72) Even by the relaxed standards of his time, he was notorious for bigotry. He routinely turned his back on Justice Cardozo because he was Jewish,
(73) he turned his back when Black lawyers argued before the Court,
(74) and when women lawyers appeared he would remark, “I see the female is here” and leave the courtroom.
(75) More to the point, McReynolds was no friend of immigrants.
(76) To put it diplomatically, he was the “improbable author” of
Two years later,
Though McReynolds conceded that the law infringed upon the school's property rights, he again emphasized that it “unreasonably interferes with the liberty of parents and guardians to direct the upbringing and education of children under their control.” (88) In support of this, he added, “The fundamental theory of liberty upon which all governments in this Union repose excludes any general power of the state to standardize its children by forcing them to accept instruction from public teachers only.” (89) The only reference to history/tradition was a clause noting that the work of religious schools had been “long regarded as useful and meritorious.” (90)
But if the state can standardize so much else in education—curriculum, textbooks, teacher certification, building certificates of occupancy—why draw the line here? For there is a substantial, irreducible element of coercion in education: students are not free to learn only the subjects that appeal to them or even to speak when they feel like it in class. What, also, exactly is meant by “fundamental theory of liberty”? Is it merely a rhetorical flourish? Of
Justice Douglas’ majority opinion for the Supreme Court struck down the law as violating the Fourteenth Amendment's equal protection clause; treating embezzlers and chicken thieves differently constitutes “a clear, pointed, unmistakable discrimination.” (93) But Douglas did not stop here. The very first sentence of his opinion highlights “a sensitive and important area of human rights,” namely, “the right to have offspring.” (94) Later, he speaks of “the basic civil rights of man,” marriage and procreation, (95) without pausing to indicate the contours of these rights. If I have a right to marry, can the state charge me for exercising that right by compelling me to purchase a marriage license? Can it force me to take a blood test? Or ban me from marrying members of my family? Is it obliged to subsidize my membership in Tinder.com, if I am unable to find a spouse on my own? Is marriage, a legal construct conferring formal benefits and obligations, actually indistinguishable from, say, freedom of speech, which does not require certification by the state? Why, in any event, refer to marriage, inasmuch as Oklahoma is not preventing Skinner from marrying? As to procreation, is this a positive right in the sense that if I have difficulty, the state is obliged to help me, for example, by funding appropriate medical procedures? Does a right to procreate imply a right not to procreate, that is, to state supplied contraception and abortion? Can a man sentenced to life in prison claim a right to impregnate his wife via artificial insemination? (96)
There is something gratuitous about the inclusion of these unenumerated rights, reminiscent of a cook tossing leftover vegetables into a stew. (97) Were they, as McReynolds would have it, based on historical practice or understanding? Douglas saw no need to pursue the question.
Justice Harlan addressed the question of unenumerated rights in some detail in his “influential”
(98) dissenting opinion in
Audaciously, Harlan's focus is not on the literal text of the Constitution, “as if we had a tax statute before us,” for the due process clause is “not self-explanatory.” (100) Instead, he proceeds from the assumption that the Constitution is “the basic charter of our society, setting out in spare but meaningful terms the principles of government.” (101) From this perspective, Harlan argues that “Each new claim to constitutional protection must be considered against a background of constitutional purpose, as they have been rationally perceived and historically developed.” (102) Hence, the due process clause should be interpreted in light of the Constitution's basic principles and purposes, in this instance, the “postulates of respect for the liberty of the individual” (103) that rule out “all substantial arbitrary impositions and purposeless restraints.” (104)
Harlan proposed a two-part test. First, is the liberty abridged fundamental, that is, does it offend “the traditions from which it developed as well as the traditions from which it broke”? (105) If the answer is yes (as it was in this case), Harlan would raise a second question, can the state's act meet the strict scrutiny test? Here, the answer was no: the Connecticut statute was “an intolerable and unjustifiable invasion of privacy in the conduct of the most intimate concerns of an individual's personal life.” (106)
Harlan's treatment of history/tradition, like a river with currents running this way and that, is no simple thing. Though he asserts that “history sheds little light” on the meaning of due process, (107) he refers to the traditions from which it developed,” and cites fourteen cases, two of which preceded the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, in support of the legitimacy of substantive due process, as well as the Framers’ views on the right to privacy implicit in the Third and Fourth Amendments. (108) At the same time, he insists that “tradition is a living thing,” and instructs us to look to “the traditions from which it broke. A decision of the Court which radically departs from [this living tradition] could not long survive, while a decision which builds on what has survived is likely to be sound.” (109) In his eyes, “liberty” is not “a series of isolated points [but] a rational continuum.” (110) With this, Harlan cannily refers simultaneously both to the past and the present.
How to answer both questions? Remarkably, Harlan did not try to hide the personal element, but began his dissent with “I” (111) and used the word no fewer than thirty-nine times and “me’ six times. Was this to suggest that he be our guide? Or merely that we must rely on justices doing their best (whatever that means)?
His dissent is a powerful counter argument to the textualism often paraded by Justice Black. Yet it has an unfinished quality, for it left practical questions unaddressed. If history sheds little light and tradition is a living thing, how can they be rigid enough to provide sufficient guidance? How to reply to differing subjective judgments?
Justice Douglas began his consideration of the merits, announcing, “We do not sit as a super-legislature to determine the wisdom, need, and propriety of laws that touch ... social conditions.” (112) He then argued that the Constitution embodies certain rights not expressly mentioned, illustrating his point with nine precedents. These “peripheral rights,” (113) implied by the expressed rights, “suggest that specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have penumbras, formed by emanations from these guarantees that help give them life and substance.” (114) He closed the case by arguing that the First (the right to associate), Third (the right to be free from being forced to quarter soldiers in one‘s home during peace time), Fourth (the right to be secure in one's person and to be free from unreasonable searches and seizures), Fifth (the privilege against self-incrimination), and Ninth (the Constitution's enumeration of rights is not necessarily exclusive) Amendments, taken together, create a zone of privacy protected by the Constitution. (115) At this point, Douglas turned to the fact that Griswold had been counseling married couples. “Would we allow the police to search the sacred precincts of marital bedrooms for telltale signs of the use of contraceptives?” he asked, following with a paean to marriage as “an association for as noble a purpose as any involved in our prior decisions.” (116) Douglas’ justification of the unenumerated right is almost entirely abstract. His sole historical reference is a clause stating, “We deal with a right of [marital] privacy older than the Bill of Rights.” (117)
The disconnect between Douglas’ argument and the facts of the case is hard to ignore. In the first place, none of the amendments or the precedents cited had the slightest relation to contraceptive counseling. Nor is running classes counseling couples obviously a private act. Nor is it clear what the “sacred precincts of marital bedrooms” refers to, for they have never been thought to constitute off limit sanctuaries barring searches for, say, contraband or weapons. (118)
No wonder Justice Black, dissenting, wrote that though he found the Connecticut law “offensive” and liked “my privacy as well as the next one ... I am nevertheless compelled to admit that government has a right to invade it unless prohibited by some specific constitutional provision.” (119) In foreswearing what Black called the “old fashioned” amending process, (120) Douglas left the right untethered to a constitutional text and denied it a legislative history, both of which might have offered useful guidance to future courts. When Black predicted that Douglas’ privacy was “a broad, abstract, and ambiguous concept which can easily be shrunken [or expanded] in meaning,” (121) he foretold its use in abortion and right to die cases as a synonym for autonomy, a rather different notion. (122) Such acts of discontinuity might seem to require unusually comprehensive justification, but for Douglas, the paragraph on penumbras and emanations seemed quite sufficient. He made no effort to rebut contrary views, for example, that the absence of a general privacy right indicates that the Constitution recognizes only the narrow privacy rights expressed in the amendments—that is, that the emanations produced no penumbra. (123)
But no, says Justice Black, dissenting, who pointed out that the Court “had never clearly held ... that proof beyond a reasonable doubt is either expressly or impliedly commanded by any provision of the Constitution.” (128) He went on to say, “The Constitution ... goes into some detail to spell out what kind of trial a defendant charged with crime should have, and I believe the Court has no power to add to or subtract from the procedures set forth by the Founders. I realize that it is far easier to substitute individual judges’ ideas of ‘fairness’ for the fairness prescribed by the Constitution, but I shall not at any time surrender my belief that the document itself should be our guide, not our own concept of what is fair, decent and right.” (129) For Black, “the only correct meaning of [due process] is that our government must proceed according to the ‘law of the land’—that is, according to written constitutional and statutory provisions as interpreted by court decisions.” (130) The alternative to the law of the land was “the law of the judges,” which is counter to the principle of democratic self-government. He does not dispute the value of the standard of proof, but merely denies that a court can enforce its opinion on the country. If there were no consensus on this question, where would it be found?
Justices Rehnquist and White, dissenting, also focused on history/tradition, pointing to states restricting abortion and to the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment as silent on the issue. In Rehnquist's words, “To reach its result, the Court necessarily has had to find within the scope of the Fourteenth Amendment a right that was apparently completely unknown to the drafters of the amendment.”
(135) Thus, while the conclusion of
Justice O’Connor, writing for a plurality of the Supreme Court, conceded that grandparents played an increasing role in the upbringing of their grandchildren, but thought “the interest of parents in the care, custody, and control of their children [are] perhaps the oldest of the fundamental liberty interests recognized by this Court.”
(136) She considered the Washington law “breathtakingly broad,” and, as there was no evidence that Granville was an unfit parent, an infringement on this fundamental right.
(137) The basis for the right was a series of precedents, including
Justices Souter and Thomas, each concurring, agreed that the parental right was well established, like O’Connor, citing a number of precedents. (138)
Justice Scalia, dissenting, resisted “the instinct against overregularizing decisions about personal relations” on the ground of “mere tradition,” as “intimate associations are complex.”
(139) The cases on which the parental right rests, chiefly
Justice Kennedy, dissenting, thought the majority ignored evolving family patterns and unwisely rejected “the best interests of the child standard [which] has been recognized for many years as a basic tool of domestic relations law in visitation proceedings.” (141) Thus, his opinion seemed simultaneously to look both forward and backward in time.
Which brings us to
Justice Alito, speaking for the Court, began with the unexceptional observation that “Constitutional analysis must begin with ‘the language of the instrument.’”
(142)
Alito rejected the notion that overruling
Chief Justice Roberts, concurring, would have upheld the law, but left the question of rejecting
Justice Kavanaugh, concurring, thought that the Constitution was “neutral” on abortion, and, therefore, that the Court must be “scrupulously neutral,” too.
(157) He emphasized that the Court had not outlawed abortion, but instead had left the question to the people and their representatives. He also reiterated Alito's point that the ruling does not cast doubt on
The concurring opinion of Justice Thomas attracted by far the most attention, apart from Alito's. He thought the due process clause “at most guarantees process,”
(159) and urged the Court to “reject substantive due process entirely.”
(160) He also believed that
Justices Breyer, Kagan, and Sotomayor, in a sixty page dissent, maintained that the Constitution put fundamental rights like abortion “off limits to majority rule.” (164) They rejected Kavanaugh's claim of neutrality, charging that the decision was a “no compromise refusal to recognize a woman's right to choose.” (165) They also feared that the same logic could be used to threaten the rights to contraception, same sex intimacy, and same sex marriage, and believed that “it undermines the Court's legitimacy.” (166)
By insisting that an unenumerated fundamental right must be both deeply rooted in the nation's traditions and essential to a scheme of ordered liberty, Alito hoped to preserve substantive due process from attacks like Thomas’, while preventing it from being used to constitutionalize subjective judicial preferences. By requiring both these tests to be met, he placed a heavy burden on rights advocates that mirrored the burden that government faced, when it sought to limit enumerated fundamental rights. He was careful to make it clear that
However, Alito's argument was undercut by his failure to analyze the very concept of ordered liberty that he pronounced essential. At one point, he indicated that the way to proceed would be to ask what the Fourteenth Amendment “means by the term.” (168) But instead of proceeding, he simply returned to the history that he thought demonstrated that abortion rights were “not deeply rooted.” (169) Cardozo had defined rights under the scheme of ordered liberty to mean that “neither liberty nor justice would exist if they were sacrificed,” (170) but Alito did not even bother to quote the words. Thus, the much vaunted “ordered liberty” test, once stated, was ignored.
Another obvious problem with the tests is that while Alito repeatedly emphasized the importance of the constitutional text, his two criteria were entirely judge-created and had no textual foundation. There is nothing odd about this. For example, the notion that fundamental rights implicate strict scrutiny is well accepted, though it also has no textual justification. More broadly, judicial review, which the Court exercised here, and the concept of fundamental rights itself also have no explicit textual basis. Alito, despite his celebration of textualism, could not avoid the snares of judicial doctrine any more than the justices he criticized.
Alito clearly believed that he was acting in the tradition of judicial self-restraint. Unelected, democratically unaccountable courts should not make policy, particularly, when the issue is morally controversial.
(171) Substantive due process had sometimes been used by justices to write their own policy preferences and ideological beliefs into the Constitution, he thought. Indeed,
Thus, Alito lined up with fetal protection laws that include fetuses as rights-bearing persons, though obviously unable to exercise such fundamental rights as freedom of speech or of religion. (174) Arguably, fetal personhood would implicate both the due process and equal protection clauses, rendering abortion unconstitutional. Kavanaugh in his concurrence declared that this radical argument was “wrong as a constitutional matter,” (175) but no other justice voiced agreement with this position, perhaps implying that it remains a live option.
“Liberty,” Alito wrote, is so “capacious”
(176) a term that it invites judges to read their own preferences into it, but the temptation should be resisted. Yet his self-restraint that entailed upholding the Mississippi statute also ironically entailed threatening well established decades old precedents, which could not be defended as embodying rights “deeply rooted” in the nation's history.
(177) Supreme Court precedents strictly bind lower courts, but
It is hard to avoid the feeling that Alito was responding not simply to a jurisprudence he believed to be profoundly flawed, but also to the social forces it seemed to embody and promote. From this perspective, the days when marriage and family were taken for granted as central supports to society are inexorably drifting away. Rates of marriage (183) and childbirth (184) continue to decline; rates of adults living alone continue to rise; (185) individualistic rights continue to be celebrated at the expense of community obligations; abortion, a facilitator of these unhealthy developments, is defended in moral terms, but in the end it is all about its liberating impact on selfish lifestyles.
For the dissenters, however, reversing precedents in
The implication of the reliance interests was that the goals of stability/predictability may sometimes be so socially valuable that they justify upholding flawed precedents.
(191) Is abortion one of these instances? In
Meanwhile, amidst a barrage of abstract issues, an empirical concern was overlooked: is there a viable basis for Alito's two-pronged test or did he simply conjure it from the ether? Consider the three precedents he cited.
Justice Powell wrote for the plurality. “When a city undertakes such intrusive regulation of the family,” he wrote, “the usual deference to the legislature is inappropriate.”
(197) As “the Constitution protects the sanctity of the family precisely because the institution of the family is deeply rooted in this nation's history and tradition,”
(198) Powell does not confine the term to “members of the nuclear family,”
(199) but concludes that “the Constitution prevents East Cleveland from standardizing its children—and its adults—by forcing all to live in certain narrowly defined family patterns.”
(200) Nowhere does Powell present empirical evidence beyond
Justice Scalia, speaking for a plurality, rejected Michael's claim because he failed to show that his alleged fundamental right was “an interest traditionally protected by our society.” (203) Had “persons in the situation of Michael and Victoria ... been treated as a protective family unit under the historical practices of our society”? (204) The answer was no: “our traditions have protected the marital family ... against the sort of claim Michael asserts.” (205) The common law as well as statutes back California's practice supporting the integrity of the family, and the presumption of legitimacy is a fundamental principle of the common law. (206) The liberty interest of an “adulterous biological father” to assert parental rights, when the child's mother is married to someone else, has never been recognized. (207) On the contrary, the presumption generally followed is the presumption of legitimacy. Since it is not a fundamental right, Michael's claim does not implicate the due process clause, and there is no reason for the Court to balance the competing claims of Michael and Gerald, who find themselves in a zero-sum situation. Rather, it is left to California to balance the claims through the ordinary political process. (208)
The level of analysis is critical here; Scalia's literal reading focused on the historically traditional rights of an adulterous natural father; had he instead spoken of parenthood, family relationships or emotional attachments, the result might have been different. (209) But Scalia's point was that the most specific tradition would be the most useful, as its applicability would be most obvious and the judicial discretion it permitted would be minimized. Utilizing a higher level of generality would “permit judges to dictate rather than discern society's views.” (210) The narrow literalness of Scalia's tradition represented his effort to enhance the utility of the concept. His opposition was not to change, he insisted, but rather to Supreme Court driven change, which he regarded as undemocratic. (211) However, in his heavy focus on history/tradition, (212) nowhere did he speak of concepts essential to ordered liberty, despite Alito's citations.
Justice Brennan, dissenting, thought Michael entitled to a hearing, and presented an extensive attack on Scalia's reliance on history/tradition. He thought the concept “malleable” and elusive, and rejected the notion that it could be located by “poring through dusty volumes on American history.” (213) Reasonable people, he wrote, “can disagree about the content of particular traditions [and] even about which traditions are relevant to the definition of ‘liberty.’” (214) There was also the question as to when “a tradition becomes firm enough to be relevant to our definition and the moment at which it becomes too obsolete to be relevant any longer.” (215) He also charged Scalia with omitting precedents that did not fit into his traditional narrative, and saw a grave level of analysis error: Scalia had asked not “whether parenthood is an interest that historically has received our attention and protection [but] whether the specific variety of parenthood—a natural father's relationship with a child whose mother is married to another—has enjoyed such protection.” (216) He pointed to earlier decisions, which protected the rights of fathers to maintain relationships with their children, even when they were born out of wedlock.
Brennan not only found tradition misapplied; he also thought that it was so inherently backward looking that it discounted important changes in society, in particular, echoing Powell, that “family” and “parenthood” have evolved and now contain a “freedom not to conform,” (217) as well as Scalia's “cramped vision.” (218) “The plurality ... squashes this freedom by requiring specific approval from history before protecting anything in the name of liberty.” (219) Scalia, in Brennan's eyes, “does not recognize that times change, does not see that sometimes a practice or rule outlives its foundations,” (220) Brennan's general hostility to the history/tradition criterion was partially undermined by his own use of history in the form of precedents and practices.
Chief Justice Rehnquist, speaking for the Court, announced that “Our established method of substantive due process analysis ... protects those fundamental rights and liberties which are, objectively. ‘deeply rooted in this nation's history and tradition’ ... and ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.’”
(222) As to history and tradition, he presented six pages covering over 700 years of Anglo-American history to show that “opposition to and condemnation of suicide—and, therefore, of assisting suicide—are consistent and enduring themes of our philosophical, legal, and cultural heritages.”
(223) These were followed by three pages listing contemporary state legislation that also condemn the practice.
(224) The purpose of the history/tradition requirement was to “rein in the subjective elements that are necessarily present in due process judicial review.”
(225) As with
Rehnquist conceded that doctors could withdraw life sustaining treatment and let nature take its course, but insisted on a distinction between killing and letting die (or what some philosophers have termed passive or active euthanasia (227)). The ruling “permits the debate to continue, as it should in a democratic society.” (228) What Alito failed to mention is that Rehnquist accepted abortion under the history/tradition and ordered liberty standards. (229)
Rehnquist's second criterion, implicit in the concept of ordered liberty, was completely undeveloped
(230) (perhaps because the failure of the history criterion rendered it superfluous) and consisted simply of a citation to
In short, none of the three cases cited by Alito as precedents for his two-pronged test in
Those considering the future might pay attention to
A federal district court in Kentucky clearly thought the policy indefensible, noting competition driven innovations it would discourage; even if a facility would cut patient costs or improve patient outcomes, it could be barred from opening. Congress had dropped its certificate of need mandate and consultants hired by Kentucky had urged the same, but the system continued. Here, there was an obvious need for a Nepali speaking agency, as Louisville had a sizable Nepali community, who were not well served by the pre-existing agencies. Applying the rational basis standard, the court asked whether the law “makes worse the very interest it purports to serve, as well as any other legitimate interest.” (234) As the law increased costs and reduced access and quality, the court found that the law failed the test. Tiwari satisfactorily stated a claim for relief under the due process clause.
Later, however, the district court, now with a new judge, ruled that Kentucky had met the rational basis standard, whereupon Tiwari appealed to the Sixth Circuit Court of Appeals, which ruled that the program “passes, perhaps with a low grade but with a pass all the same.” (235) The law may fail to meet its goals, but this is insufficient to require a judicial correction “Our custom instead is to assume that democracy will eventually fix the problem.” (236) Whether there is a right to earn a living “is for the U.S. Supreme Court, not our court, to make.” (237) The Supreme Court subsequently denied certiorari. (238)
The right to earn a living has decided discredited
The Constitution, as an astute observer once observed, “was born of prudent compromise rather than principle, ... derived more from experience than from doctrine, and ... was received with an ambivalence in no small part attributable to its ambiguities.” (239) Disagreement thus was guaranteed, not only as to what provisions mean but more basically, how the meaning was to be ascertained. Plainly, the matter cannot simply be left to the good graces of well-meaning judges sitting as Platonic philosopher-kings. It is obvious, then, that courts require some principle to guide their determination of unenumerated fundamental rights. The most frequently applied criterion is a deeply rooted historical/traditional consensus, which is thought to provide a strong, stable, and satisfactory criterion. The fact of consensus naturally minimizes the likelihood of controversy, always a major plus in designating fundamental rights.
Though the justices do not mention it, the criterion itself is deeply rooted in Western intellectual history and tradition. In considering the bases of authority, for example, Max Weber assigned the pride of place to “an established belief in the sanctity of immemorial traditions and the legitimacy of those exercising authority under them.” (240) Longstanding cultural patterns, likely unwritten, legitimate the exercise of power, generating an emotional respect that is validated by the venerability of the practice itself. Is it unthinking habit or the deliberate adherence to exemplary norms? It hardly matters. The momentum generated by tradition is strong, indeed, sometimes unstoppable.
The Anglo-Irish politician, Edmund Burke, considered history/tradition not only an important source of legitimacy, but also, in general, a social blessing. Thus, he wrote of the British constitution that its “sole authority is that it has existed time out of mind,” (241) as this indicated that multiple generations had found it, overall, useful and appropriate. A nation is not created and ruled by pure reason, he observed, but represents “a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead and those who are to be born.” (242) The ties of obligation go both backward and forward; the purpose of change is preservation. A constitution, thus, is a product of “many minds in many ages. It is no simple, no superficial thing, nor to be estimated by superficial understandings” (243) [because] a nation ...is an idea of continuity, which extends in time [and] is made by the peculiar circumstances, occasions, tempers, dispositions, and moral, civil, and social habitudes of the people, which disclose themselves only in a long space of time.” (244)
Burke was especially impressed by the argument from prudence, which he considered “not only first in rank of the virtues political and moral, but […] the director, the regulator, the standard of them all.” (245) He felt “a presumption in favor of any settled scheme of government,” (246) fearing that disregarding history in preference to theoretical rumination may result in unanticipated consequences that bring with them serious harm; abstract disputations may call into question the most profound matters, perhaps opening the door to demagogues or authoritarians. Modest incremental change drawing on history/tradition is the prudent path.
Burke's views point to a certain incoherence in Alito's argument. Like Burke, he is impressed with history/tradition as a legitimator and teacher. Relatedly, he might think it an unrealistic act of hubris to imagine that Hamilton's judiciary, “the least dangerous branch,”
(247) can be the chief engine of social progress. Yet unlike Burke, he seems blind to the advantages of incrementalism, as exhibited in his dismissal of Roberts’ position. In this, Alito may mirror larger patterns in judicial behavior. It is true that apparently revolutionary rulings in hindsight may be seen as culminating a lengthy incremental process. The famous
Alito made it clear that the practical consequences of the ruling were not properly his charge, retorting that “how our political system or society will respond to [the] decision” is not the Court's concern. (253) The justices must “only do [their] job ... to interpret the law.“ (254) In this, he seemed to resemble Weber's politician adopting an ethic of ultimate ends, who will do what is right and “leave the results to the Lord.” Weber contrasts this approach with an ethic of responsibility, which must take “account of the foreseeable results of one's actions.” (255) The problem with Alito's ethic of ultimate ends is that as rights are not absolute, determining their limitations inescapably entails considering the practical results of the law. Thus, an empirical analysis of all the cases decided by the Court in the 2020–2021 term “found that Justices who decry consequentialism or pragmatism often ended up making consequentialist arguments themselves.” (256) Alito might grant the power of Weber's distinction, but add a pair of points in rebuttal, first, that it applies to politicians, not to judges; and second, that it ignores the difference between a choice that is merely morally disagreeable and one that is morally criminal. (257) For Alito, it is plain that choosing abortion is morally criminal. Thus, his declaration: “we cannot embrace a narrow ground of decision simply because it is narrow; it must also be right.” (258)
Does Alito's emphasis on history/tradition impede the updating of the Constitution? The difficulty with the passive voice, of course, is that the actor is omitted. The Constitution does not update itself, but instead, must be updated by unelected and therefore democratically unaccountable judges. When they change the meaning of statutes or regulations, they effectively change the law; in other words, they assume a function the Constitution reserves for the openly political branches. Occasionally, this may be justified to avoid an absurdity. Article II designates the President commander in chief of the army and navy; it would be bizarre to insist on a constitutional amendment to include the air force. Similarly, when the Third Amendment refers to quartering soldiers without the consent of the owner of the house, it is hard to imagine that it does not also apply to sailors. But these absurdities are rare and usually easy to identify. As Justice Thomas put it, “Reliance on history to inform the meaning of constitutional text is more legitimate, and more administrable, than asking judges to make difficult empirical judgments.” (259)
Yet in the end, the reliance on history/tradition fails to persuade. For one thing, the worship of the past seems an odd preoccupation in a country that has always celebrated The New. Lacking the ancient roots of Britain, America from the earliest days has focused on the future, seeing tomorrow more as opportunity than as snare. Recall Crevecoeur's American man: self-reliant, practical, hopeful. (260) What to traditionalists has seemed good common sense has frequently seemed to many Americans a communitarian romanticism blocking individual-driven progress, the work of fuddy-duddies with nothing but vapid nostalgia to offer.
For relying on a historical/traditional consensus is by definition backward looking and subject to the defects of such an approach. It may, for example, entail relying on decisions taken when large segments of society were effectively excluded from the political process, and is thus inherently biased against these people. To answer whether abortion is a right in the context of the Fourteenth Amendment, for instance, is to anchor it to a time dominated by the view that women are properly subordinate to and dependent on men, who alone could satisfactorily represent their interests, a view that denied women the vote and attenuated their political influence. Thus, the views of women on a supremely important issue that affects only them directly is made quite irrelevant. On the other hand, to tie abortion rights to the feminist tradition, which may be connected to the equal protection clause, will yield an emphatically different result. (261) An originalist focusing on the original public meaning of the text of the Fourteenth Amendment might favor the more literal first tradition, but there will be many who believe it has been superseded by the second, which seems to them clearly more robust today. How to choose between competing traditions?
In short, the plea to rely on history/tradition must partly rise or fall on the particular history/tradition selected. When the white South invoked it on behalf of slavery or later on behalf of segregation (or The Southern Way of Life), it was eventually properly rejected. The apparent historical/traditional consensus, at least among the white population, was dismissed as irrelevant. Today's justices naturally do not propose reverting to a brazenly racist past, but taking history/tradition as a legitimating variable will leave them open to embracing a range of problematic arguments. As one careful analyst noted, “Judges working within a traditionalist framework will often narrow or broaden a tradition with the aim either to exclude or include the practice being reviewed.” (262) In order to avoid this fate, justices are forced to pick and choose among the various histories/traditions proffered, enshrining an element of subjectivity and discretion that calls into question the entire enterprise.
It is also plain that a Burkean argument for history/tradition-based incrementalism comes perilously close to an argument for the status quo; formalizing the consensus on rights may minimize conflict and confusion, but it will change things so little that it may hardly be worth the trouble. As Justice Brennan put it, “if the only purpose of the due process clause is to confirm the importance of interests already protected,” it becomes a “redundancy [that] mocks those who ... wrote the Fourteenth Amendment.” (263) With this narrow reading, the due process clause will offer scant protection to nonconformists, protecting mainly those who need no protection. Put differently, Alito would have the Court safeguard rights generally accepted and not endangered, rather than generate new ones. (264)
Of course, Alito's point is not that he is opposed to change but merely to an unaccountable, undemocratic Supreme Court as the driver of change. If the goal is to be flexible and accommodating, he might ask, why have a constitution, which can only be an obstacle to change? Why not follow the British model and grant all power to the legislature? All of which is to rehearse familiar arguments for a living Constitution able to adapt to change and free society from the dead hand of the past.
There are also technical questions concerning the historical/traditional consensus. Why assume that a consensus supporting a practice is indistinguishable from one viewing it as a judicially enforceable fundamental constitutional right? The consensus may be merely permissive, not mandatory, and the right may not rise to the level of fundamental. There is a consensus supporting driving on the right side of the road, but it is hard to imagine it as a constitutional right. Why assume that if a state has not outlawed a practice, it recognizes it as a right? Perhaps it was simply an oversight. Or a sign of indifference.
There is also the level of analysis problem. A historical/traditional consensus covering the literal facts of the case may seem the most persuasive, but its wider application will necessarily be problematical, undercutting its significance. If
Too, complications inhere in the historical enterprise itself, which Eliot famously found “mixing memory and desire.”
(265) Thus, in one of his last opinions, Justice Breyer catalogued a series of practical problems that, together, left the emphasis on historical/traditional consensus in tatters.
(266) Judges are not historians, he pointed out, suggesting that their law office history will too often be inadequate, perhaps merely the uncritically accepted work of
Thus far, history and tradition have been literally joined by a slash, for the justices have generally treated them as essentially the same. However, “history” and “tradition” are not synonyms, though the words are obviously related and would seem to overlap. If history, very roughly speaking, refers to what happened, tradition refers to the narrative we have constructed about what we believe happened, often a narrative with a normative point. (269) These narratives may help to shape our opinions, beliefs, and values, as well as our very identities. Thus, while there may be only one objective history, there will always be a plethora of traditions reflecting differences in perspectives, self-interest, memories, and numerous other factors.
Yet Alito and others on the Court persist in ignoring all this messiness, addressing history and tradition, typically the centerpieces of unenumerated rights analysis, in a stunningly casual manner. Sometimes, in fact, “history and tradition” seems like an example of a hendiadys, a figure of speech in which words joined by a conjunction convey a single meaning, like “nice and easy.” Omitting or muddying the distinctions between history and tradition and treating them as unidimensional and linear have the practical advantage of simplifying the task of argumentation. But the price is high, for this approach downplays the differences, the multiple dimensions, the zigging and zagging, and to that extent may be seriously unrealistic and misleading. What is absent from the argumentation is precisely what demands emphasis, and these considerations are not peripheral or trivial, but clearly basic. If the Court has not confronted these questions, it is hard to take seriously its repeated reassurances that it will be guided by history/tradition, concepts that it has barely begun to investigate. As Tallulah Bankhead reported in a very different context, “There is less in this than meets the eye.” (270)
In sum, though historical/traditional consensus sounds commonsensical, it does not take much effort to reveal its shortcomings. Which raises the question as to its alternatives; the old cliché is that you can’t beat something with nothing. The chief alternative seems to be citing cases that are presented as pertinent. There is a circularity here, as the Court justifies a finding in terms of prior findings by the Court, which themselves may have hardly had justifications worth discussing.
At other times, the Court, in imitation of the introduction of the Ten Commandments, has simply announced that certain unenumerated rights exist. To those seeking justifications, the Court in its silence appears to echo Ring Lardner's riposte: “Shut up, he explained.” (271)
If the bases of unenumerated rights were merely of antiquarian interest, none of these problems would matter much. But, of course, the situation is entirely the reverse. Many of the most high profile, impactful, and controversial cases of the past few decades have pivoted on exactly this concept. Commentators focusing on the product, not the process, have often lost sight of this. But that the notion of unenumerated rights remains so intellectually undeveloped in the light of its obvious importance is one of the most glaring shortfalls in modern constitutional law.
King Lear, act I, sc. 1, line 99.
Chicago, Burlington & Quincy Railroad v. Chicago, 166 U.S. 226.
Barron v. Baltimore, 7 Pet. 243 (1833).
J
B
One argument offered at the constitutional convention against a bill of rights was that the delegates might fail to identify all the rights; the listing of some would imply the exclusion of others.
1 Ann. of Cong. 439 (Gales & Seaton eds. 1834). Or as perhaps the preeminent historian of early America put it, the purpose of the Ninth Amendment was to ensure “a universe of rights, possessed by the people, latent rights still to be evoked and enacted into law.” B
4 C
C
C
B
B
B
C
Paul Finkelman,
T
I
S
Troxel v. Granville, 530 U.S. 57, 91 (2000).
R
J
Calvin R. Massey,
381 U.S. 479, 492 (1965).
Alfred H. Kelly,
Lash,
Kurt T. Lash,
Black speculates that the Amendment might have been ignored for years because of its implications for slavery. A New Birth of Freedom,
142 S. Ct. 2228.
Barron,
Amend. XIV, sec. 1.
268 U.S. 652, 666.
D
283 U.S. 697, 707.
293 U.S. 245, 262. “There needs be no attempt to enumerate or comprehensively to define what is included in the ‘liberty’ protected by the due process clause,” Butler declared.
299 U.S. 353, 365
330 U.S. 1, 8–16.
333 U.S. 257, 273, 278.
N.Y. State labor law, sec. 10.
Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U.S. 578, 590 (1897), qtg. Bradley, J., Butchers’ Union Co. v. Crescent City Co., 111 U.S. 746, 762 (1884). This was an ironic precursor to Charles Black's Ninth Amendment argument. The two plainly would have agreed on little else.
198 U.S. 45, 57.
O
Lochner
Dobbs,
Max Crema & Lawrence B. Solum,
Murray's Lessee v. Hoboken Land & Improvement Co., 59 U.S. 272, 276 (1856).
Dred Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. 393, 450 (1857).
Nebr. Laws 1919, c. 249.
I.N. Edwards,
262 U.S. 390, at 402.
Qtd. In A
P
A
H
Robert L. Carter,
J
United States v. Manzi, 276 U.S. 463, 467 (1928); Chang Chan v. Nagle, 268U.S. 346, 353 (1925); United States v. Ginsberg, 243 U.S. 472, 475 (1917).
Louise Weinberg,
576 U.S. 644, at 668 (2015)
561 U.S. 742, 793 (2010).
539 U.S. 558, 593 (2003).
521 U.S. 702, 720 (1997).
505 U.S. 833, 848 (1992).
497 U.S. 261, 342 (1990).
468 U.S. 609, 618 (1984).
Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 152–53 (1973).
Meyer, s
Oreg. Ls., sec. 5259.
Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U.S. 510, at 534–35 (1925). McReynolds comes perilously close to asserting that parents owned their children.
Pierce,
Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U.S. 110, at 142 (1989).
Okla. Stat. Ann. Tit. 57, sec. 171
316 U.S. 535, at 541.
Gerber v. Hickman, 264 F. 3d 882 (9th Cir. 2001).
On the other hand, Douglas ignored the opportunity to reverse the notorious pro-eugenics
Obergefell,
The case has been cited 665 times in federal courts and 213 times in state courts.
367 U.S. 497, at 540.
Poe,
Griswold,
Griswold
The Court abandoned the marriage rationale in Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972), even extending the right to contraceptives to minors, Carey v. Pop. Servs. Int’l., 431 U.S. 678 (1977).
Thomas Halper,
As “penumbra” refers to partial shadows, as from an eclipse, it is not clear that even metaphorically it could give anything life. In his chambers, Justice Thomas has a plaque reading, “Please don’t emanate in the penumbra.” David J. Garrow,
397 U.S. 358, 361.
Texas Penal Code, arts. 1191–94, 1196.
Roe,
In the second paragraph, Blackmun says that abortion is the subject of vigorous debate among physicians, and then details the history of medical opinion, with special attention paid to the views of the American Medical Association (
Roe,
Troxel,
Dobbs,
Dobbs,
Dobbs,
Casey,
Dobbs,
If the criteria are history/tradition and ordered liberty, it is hard to understand why precedents in these areas warrant a waiver. Alito's response, which introduces a pair of entirely different criteria, is really no response at all, but instead merely a means to avoid further controversy.
Roberts has not always practiced what he preached. For example, he wrote for the Court in Citizens United, a high profile case that overruled precedents and generated substantial criticism from officials, pundits, academics, and others. Citizens United v. FEC, 558 U.S. 310 (2010).
A well-respected reporter covering the Court has written that Roberts tried to persuade Kavanaugh and Barrett to decide for Mississippi but uphold Roe. She doubts he would have succeeded, but believes that leaking Alito's opinion made it all but impossible. Joan Biskupic,
Dobbs,
Dobbs,
Douglas T. Kendall,
Dobbs
302 U.S. 319, 325.
Dobbs,
Palko,
Ironically, though the majority boasted that returning abortion to the states was a victory for democracy (
Dobbs,
On this basis, from 1973–2005 in some 413 cases pregnancy was an essential factor leading to criminal prosecution of women. Lynn M. Paltrow & Jeanne Flavin,
Dobbs,
Amy Coney Barrett,
But
Dobbs,
D
A
Marriage rates dropped from 9.8/1000 in 1990 to 5.1 in 2020. Erin Duffin,
Birth rates dropped from 15.573/1000 in 1990 to 12.012 in 2021. M
Rates grew from 12.8% (23.2 million) in 1990 to 14.4% (36.2 million) in 2020. U.S. C
Bendix Autolite Corp. v. Midweco Enters., 486 U. S. 888, 897–98 (1988); David Lyons,
Moragne v. States Marine Lines, 398 U.S. 375, at 403 (1970).
Randy J. Kozel,
“Legislatures are constantly creating new legal rules,” one analyst observed, “yet no one thinks that this somehow gives those aggrieved by the new rule some vested legal right in the continuation of the prior legal regime.” Michael Stokes Paulsen,
Burnet v. Colorado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 405 (1932). Brandeis could hardly have been referring to a topic as weighty and controversial as abortion.
An example would be the Slaughterhouse Cases, almost universally reviled, yet a century and a half later not overturned. 83 U.S. 36 (1873). As Scalia demanded during oral argument, “Why are you asking us to overrule 150, 140 years of prior law, when you can reach your result under substantive due process.?” Transcript of Oral Argument, at 6, McDonald v. Chicago, 561 U.S. 742 (2010). By closing off the privileges and immunities path, this case was critical in the application of substantive due process to the states. Justice Thomas, like Charles Black, would prefer reversing Slaughterhouse and substantive due process in favor of privileges and immunities, one of their few areas of agreement. Thomas,
Casey,
Dobbs,
Rehnquist had argued in Casey that women who lacked access to abortions could take care that they did not become pregnant. Casey,
A non-representative online panel surveyed before and after Alito's draft opinion was leaked to the press revealed that respondents perceived Americans to be more supportive of abortion following the leak, and that social liberals trusted the Court less. Opinions on abortion were unchanged. Chelsey S. Clark & Elizabeth Levy Paluck,
413 U.S. 494, 499.
Nat’l Vital Stat. Sys. (2022).
Michael H.,
Burnham v. Superior Court, 495 U.S. 604, at 626 (1990).
Scalia explicitly address the issue of historical methodology. Michael H.,
Michael H.,
Wash. Rev. Code sec. 9A.36.060(10.
Washington,
James Rachels,
Washington,
The case's syllabus claims that the “various descriptions of the interest here at stake --
Obergefell,
Ky. Rev. Stat. sec. 216B.061(1) and sec. 216B.020.
Civil Action No. 3:19-CV-884-JRW-CHL.
Tiwari v. Friedlander, 26 F. 4th 355, 363 (2022).
Tiwari v. Friedlandfer, 143 S. Ct. 444 (2022).
Philip B. Kurland,
M
E
E
E
E
B
T
Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
D
384 U.S. 436.
376 U.S. 254.
Dobbs,
From M
V
Bernard Williams,
Dobbs,
N.Y. State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n. v. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. 2111, 2130 (2022). Thomas does not notice that relying on history itself involves judges making difficult empirical judgments.
J. H
Ruth Bader Ginsberg,
Marc O. DeGirolami,
Michael H,
Progressive constitutionalists, on the other hand, “view the power and normative authority of some social groups over others as the fruit of illegitimate private hierarchy. And regard the Constitution as one important mechanism for challenging those entrenched private orders.” Robin West,
T.S. E
N.Y. Rifle & Pistol Ass’n., Inc.,
For example, three medieval historians have charged that Alito's opinion in Dobbs misunderstood some key terms used by English lawyers in the thirteenth century. Karl Shoemaker, Mireille Pardon & Sara McDougall,
Philip B. Kurland,
Marc O. DeGirolami believes that “when the Court interprets traditionally, it signals the presumptive influence of political and cultural practices of substantial duration.”
Qtd. in A
R