Published Online: Aug 04, 2020
Page range: 233 - 260
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2478/bjals-2020-0011
Keywords
© 2020 Julian R Murphy, published by Sciendo
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 License.
The rule that penal statutes are to be interpreted strictly, also known as the rule of lenity (“the rule”), has been said to be as old as the task of statutory interpretation itself. (1) It has also been labelled “the subject of more constant controversy than perhaps of any in the whole circle of the Law.” (2) All agree (3) that the rule found early expression in the practice of 17th century English courts strictly construing statutes that purported to displace the “benefit of clergy” (a common law doctrine that provided exceptions to the death penalty for certain eligible defendants and crimes). (4) Some even seek to trace the origins of the rule to Byzantine times. (5) Despite its shared ancestry, the rule has evolved in different ways in most common law jurisdictions. This article will explore some of these differences by tracing the origins and evolution of the rule in two illustrative contexts – Australia and the United States.
A comparison between Australian and the United States has at least three reasons to recommend it. First, both the Australian and United States’ rules share the same source, namely, the common law of England. Secondly, apart from both being common law systems, Australia and the United States share a number of relevant constitutional features, notably: a written constitution; a separation of legislative, judicial and executive power; and a federal structure. The third reason to believe that a comparison between the two jurisdictions might prove informative is that that Australian judges discussing the rule regularly draw upon decisions of the United States Supreme Court. (6)
This article will proceed in four parts. First, some terminological clarifications and a statement of the scope of the rule for the purposes of this article. Secondly, a discussion of the rule's origin and development in Australia. Thirdly, a discussion of the United States context. Finally, an effort to explain the similarities and divergences in the evolution of the rule in Australia and the United States.
Before launching into the discussion proper it is necessary to clarify some of the terms used in this article. The first point of clarification pertains to the rule's title, or shorthand label. In Australia, the rule is rarely referred to as the rule of lenity,
(7) and is more commonly described as the rule that “where there is doubt about the meaning of a penal statute it should be resolved in favour of the subject”.
(8) In the United States, the rule is now most commonly referred to as “the rule of lenity”.
(9) The American phraseology remains a modern phenomenon, dating back only to 1958.
(10) Prior to that time, the rule was generally called the rule of strict construction or, in the fuller sense, “[t]he rule that penal laws are to be construed strictly”.
(11) The modern move away from the language of “strict construction” is a welcome development, as that label was apt to confuse. This is because, according to a holistic conception of the rule, while ambiguous provisions creating criminal liability will be construed strictly (against the State), ambiguous provisions
Unfortunately, titular matters are not the only aspects of the rule requiring clarification; courts in Australia and the United States tend to be somewhat undecided on two further questions:
what is meant by “penal” laws – i.e. what type of statutes engage the rule?; and what is meant by “ambiguity” – i.e. what degree of statutory ambiguity is required before the rule is engaged?
In Australia, there does not appear to be consensus as to the sort of statute that will engage the rule. (16) In general, invocations of the rule refer simply to “penal” statutes. (17) More specific articulations of the rule sometimes refer to “statutes creating offences”, (18) or statutes that have “enlarged” an offence or that might be read as “extending any penal category”. (19) Nevertheless, the rule has also been applied to non-criminal statutes, for example, legislation pertaining to government powers of property confiscation (20) and deportation. (21) Further difficulties arise when a statute contains an amalgam of penal and remedial provisions. (22)
In the United States, the position appears to be no clearer. Although the courts agree that the rule is engaged by all “criminal statutes”,
(23) there is uncertainty as to the application of the rule to hybrid statutes incorporating both criminal and civil provisions.
(24) This uncertainty has been compounded by the ill-defined interaction of
The final terminological issue warranting mention is the “ambiguity” precondition to the rule's application. (27) How much ambiguity is required before a statute will be deemed ambiguous for the purposes of the rule? (28) In Australia, the threshold requirement for ambiguity has found varied expression. For instance, the High Court has suggested that all that is needed to engage the rule is “doubt about the meaning of a penal statute”. (29) Earlier case law required “a fair and reasonable doubt” about the meaning of statutory language before the rule would be engaged. (30) The most recent pronouncement of the High Court on the topic suggests that what is needed is “real” ambiguity. (31) In America, Justice Scalia, writing extra-judicially with Bryan Garner, called for a similar threshold test: “The criterion we favour is this: whether, after all the legitimate tools of interpretation have been applied, ‘a reasonable doubt persists’.” (32) Others in the United States have said that “grievous ambiguity” is required before the rule can be engaged. (33) Yet others have said that the rule is engaged “only when the equipoise of competing reasons cannot otherwise be resolved.” (34) For present purposes, it is sufficient to acknowledge the controversy over the meaning of “ambiguity” rather than attempt to resolve it.
A number of early decisions of the High Court make reference to the rule. An illuminating example is the case of
Of the majority, Chief Justice Griffith did not find the statute to be ambiguous and, accordingly, held that the rule was not engaged. Nevertheless, in obiter dicta, his Honour noted that in “a case of ambiguity … the construction in favour of liberty should be adopted.”
(42) Justice Barton engaged more substantively with the rule, referring to Blackstone
(43) and three separate English authorities.
(44) The burden of Justice Barton's observations was that the rule required that the court not “strain” the words of a penal statute to extend it beyond those acts “distinctly” or “strictly” within the “plain meaning of the words used”.
(45) Importantly, for Justice Barton, where statutory words permit of two equally plausible interpretations, the courts must prefer that which favors the defendant.
(46) Justice O’Connor reached the same conclusion as the majority without explicitly referring to the rule. Instead, his Honour invoked the separation of powers concerns animating the rule:
“where a Statute constitutes the committing of certain acts a criminal offence … [it is not] the duty of a Court to so add to the language of a Statute as to make it include the committing of acts of the same kind which lead to the same result, but which the legislature has not constituted an offence. To do so would be to make laws, not to interpret them.”
(47)
What the various opinions in
On the other side of the conceptual divide, Justice Isaacs conceived of a less powerful rule, which would only come into play if legislative intent could not be relied upon to clarify ambiguous words. This view found support in the extended treatment of the rule by Justice O’Connor in “The existence of an ambiguity in the words to be construed does not necessarily create a doubt. It is a reason for an examination of the context, the scope and object of the enactment. But that examination may satisfy the Court beyond all doubt as to the meaning to be placed on an expression which is on its face ambiguous. I take it, therefore, that in the interpretation of a penal or taxing Statute
In the years since “The rule formerly accepted, that statutes creating offences are to be strictly construed, has lost much of its importance in modern times. In determining the meaning of a penal statute the ordinary rules of construction must be applied, but if the language of the statute remains ambiguous or doubtful the ambiguity or doubt may be resolved in favour of the subject by refusing to extend the category of criminal offences … The rule is perhaps one of last resort.”
(61)
Nevertheless, before leaving these cases it is worth noting that, in the final result in
Unlike the United States – to be discussed below – Australian courts very rarely suggest that the rule might have a constitutional dimension. It will be recalled, however, that in the earliest High Court case to authoritatively apply the rule,
An important aspect of Australian statutory interpretation is the role played by what this article will call “interpretation statutes”, which statutes contain legislative directives as to how courts should engage in the task of statutory interpretation. Each jurisdiction in Australia has enacted such a statute, (68) and each includes a purposive interpretation provision. (69) Broadly speaking, there are two varieties of purposive interpretation provisions. (70) For present purposes, the more prescriptive variety of provision needs to be considered, because if the rule can be squared with such a provision then it will certainly be reconcilable with the less prescriptive provision.
An example of the more prescriptive provision can be seen in §15AA of the federal “In interpreting a provision of an Act, the interpretation that would best achieve the purpose or object of the Act (whether or not that purpose or object is expressly stated in the Act) is to be preferred to each other interpretation.”
(71) “ (1) Subject to subsection (2), where a provision of an Act is reasonably open to more than one construction, a construction that would promote the purposes or object of the Act (whether or not that purpose or object is expressly stated in the Act) must be preferred to a construction that would not promote that purpose or object.
In summary, the Australian rule of lenity is a common law creature (albeit with ill-defined constitutional roots) that has been largely unaffected by the legislative enactment of purposive interpretation provisions. Nevertheless, the Australian rule is one of “last resort”, only applied after other interpretative methods have been exhausted and “ambiguity or doubt” remains. (78) The rule has been understood and applied in this way in recent years. (79)
The rule first entered the federal law reports of the Supreme Court of the United States in 1820 via Chief Justice John Marshall's judgment in
The strong, textualist version of the rule articulated in
Notwithstanding the fact that, prior to
Historians of the rule in America have described how the
The second chapter in Solan's 20th Century history of the rule is set in the Rehnquist Supreme Court (1986—2005). This period saw the rule have something of a renaissance, largely as a result of the championship of Justice Scalia.
(99) Yet the relative frequency of the rule's invocation did not translate into a stronger statement of its place in the interpretative process. In fact, for most members of the Court the rule came “dead last in the interpretative hierarchy.”
(100) So, for example, in
As was foreshadowed above, the Court in “The rule that penal laws are to be construed strictly … is founded on the tenderness of the law for the rights of individuals; and on the plain principle that the power of punishment is vested in the legislative, not in the judicial department. It is the legislature, not the Court, which is to define a crime, and ordain its punishment.”
(106)
With the words “vested in the legislative”, one sees a clear reliance on the separation of powers doctrine and an unwillingness on the part of the federal judiciary to venture into Congress’ sovereign domain of criminal lawmaking.
(107) Astute scholars
(108) have noted the
Even without accepting Kahan's claims about the specific connections between “because of the seriousness of criminal penalties, and because criminal punishment usually represents the moral condemnation of the community, legislatures and not courts should define criminal activity … Thus, where there is ambiguity in a criminal statute, doubts are resolved in favour of the defendant.”
(116)
Today, the rule is commonly understood to be grounded in a second constitutional imperative—Due Process.
(117) More specifically, the rule is said to arise from the idea inherent in Due Process that a person ought to have sufficient notice, or fair warning, of the acts that a government would criminalize.
(118) At least two scholars
(119) have suggested that the Due Process foundation of the rule was present in
In “it is reasonable that fair warning should be given to the world in language that the common world will understand, of what the law intends to do if a certain line is passed. To make the warning fair, so far as possible the line should be clear.”
(124)
The final constitutional dimension to the rule of lenity is, arguably, the effect it gives to values of federalism. On this account, federal criminal laws ought to be interpreted strictly so as to limit the scope of federal legislative incursion into regulatory realms traditionally left to the states. Kahan articulates the values underlying this reasoning in the following terms:
“What conduct a state chooses to criminalize and how severely it chooses to punish it are matters critical to the experience of deliberative democracy within that state. Because federal criminal law dictates uniform, national answers to such questions, expansive readings of federal criminal law threaten to extinguish the opportunity that states have to use criminal law to express and shape local ideals.”
(127)
Just as the rule has arguably been impacted by statutory innovations in Australia so too have legislative enactments in the United States proved troubling for courts applying the rule and scholars theorizing it. At least two states have legislated to codify the rule: Florida and Ohio.
(131) The vast majority, however, have done the opposite – attempting to displace the rule by statute. This started in the early 1800s, when Tennessee and Virginia gaming laws required courts to interpret them “remedially”, despite their penal character.
(132) The first generally applicable statutory provision purporting to displace the rule came into effect in Arkansas in 1838.
(133) In Livingston Hall's invaluable survey of the rule's early legislative modification he describes how other states soon followed suit at the recommendation of “commissioners appointed to revise the penal codes of the older states, or draft new ones for territories on their admission to statehood”.
(134) In 1864 such a rule was proposed in New York where Field, Noyes and Bradford's “The rule of the common law that penal statutes are to be strictly construed according to the fair import of their terms, has no application to this Code. All its provisions are to be construed according to the fair import of their terms, with a view to effect its objects and to promote justice.”
In the federal context, there is no analog to the state purposive interpretation provisions. That is not to say that such a thing has not been contemplated. The American Law Institute's Model Penal Code excludes the Rule, providing: “when the language [of a Code provision] is susceptible of differing constructions it shall be interpreted to further the general purposes [of the Code] and the special purposes of the particular provision involved.” (138) Whether such a wide-reaching prescription could garner sufficient congressional support to pass into law remains to be seen. Furthermore, there would likely be a challenge to the constitutional validity of such a law, given the Due Process and separation of powers concerns that the rule is said to embody. (139)
Although there has not yet been a federal effort to comprehensively displace the rule, there have been attempts at more targeted modification of the rule in particular contexts, such as racketeering and securities fraud.
(140) The most notable of these attempts is contained in the
Notwithstanding general agreement about the common law and constitutional foundations of the rule there is rarely agreement on the Supreme Court as to its application. One scholar has written that “The rule of lenity today has very little practical effect in decisions interpreting criminal statutes”
(148), another claims “Today, strict construction survives more as a makeweight for results that seem right on other grounds than as a consistent policy of statutory interpretation.”
(149) Before he was elevated to the Supreme Court, Justice Kavanaugh admitted “I do not have a firm idea about how to handle the rule of lenity. Of course, the Supreme Court seems to be very uncertain about the rule of lenity, too.”
(150) Yet the Court continues to refer to the rule and purport to apply it.
(151) If application of the rule appears “random”
(152) that is likely because of the diversification of interpretative tools and methodologies now in use.
(153) This is not a problem unique to the rule. In a thorough survey of the Supreme Court's approach to statutory interpretation, one scholar summarized the approach as “eclectic”.
(154) While the rule has been subjected to sustained academic criticism – including some prominent voices calling for its abolishment
(155) – there has never been serious doubt in the Supreme Court that the tiebreaker version of the rule is sound. Recent cases suggest as much, with the rule dictating the result for a closely split Court in
As has been seen, early statements of the rule in Australia and the United States both gave it real force as a tool engaged in the face of any textual ambiguity in penal statutes. On both of these accounts, textual ambiguity could not easily be resolved by reference to the overarching purpose of the statute. Instead, both accounts stressed the need for clarity in the words of criminal statutes and thought it proper to apply the rule in the absence of such textual clarity. In Australia, that initial position was complicated by the persuasive reasoning of Justice Isaacs’ dissent in
Perhaps the starkest difference in the rule's development in Australia and the United States is that only in the latter country has the rule gained a constitutional foothold. The first, and most obvious, reason for this difference is that Australia's Constitution contains no provision comparable to the Due Process clauses contained in the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution.
(157) Less easy to explain is the failure of Australian courts to conceive of the rule as an expression of the separation of powers. It is true that Justice O’Connor in
In contrast, the rule has been expressed in constitutional terms in the United States for close to two centuries—primarily in furtherance of separation of powers and Due Process values, but also, occasionally, for federalism-orientated reasons. Nevertheless, there is no agreement amongst the academy as to whether the rule is merely constitutionally inspired or whether it is in fact a constitutional requirement. So, for example, Ross Davies calls the rule a “quasi-constitutional norm” as distinct from a “truly constitutional standard”. (159) Einer Elhauge describes the constitutional foundations of the rule as “dubious”. (160) This analysis would seem to be borne out by the fact that the rule has been subject to legislative displacement in many of the states. (161)
There is significant diversity of approach to the rule amongst Australia's state and federal legislatures, just as there is in the United States. Two Australian states have legislated to preserve the rule,
(162) while at least two American states have enshrined the rule in their own statutory provisions.
(163) At the federal level, Australia has an overarching liberal construction clause while the United States Congress has preferred to enact targeted liberal construction clauses within specific pieces of penal legislation, like
Finally, it is surprising to note that the current versions of the rule in Australia and the United States share very much in common despite their distinct routes of historical development. Both countries have grappled with the application of the rule to hybrid civil-criminal statutes; both countries have struggled to identify the precise degree of “ambiguity” or “doubt” required to engage the rule; and both countries have placed the rule last in the interpretative hierarchy – as a “last resort” (165) in Australia and a “tiebreaker” in the United States.
This article has sought to survey the genesis and development of the rule of lenity (or the rule that ambiguous penal laws be interpreted in favor of the subject) in Australia and the United States. This descriptive analysis has revealed some significant doctrinal differences in each country's development of the rule, primarily deriving from local constitutional differences. In the knowledge of these differences, it is surprising to see how closely the two countries’ contemporary versions of the rule align—the United States using the language of “tie-breaker” and Australia using the language of “last resort.” These linguistically similar formulations have been arrived at despite very little modern reference to decisions of the other country's case law. The question left unanswered by this analysis is, of course, the most interesting. Why is it that the rule has achieved such a similar state in both countries despite the local differences? The answer to this question is best left for future research.
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 95 (1820) (“The rule that penal laws are to be construed strictly, is perhaps not much less old than construction itself.”).
J
Modern historians of the rule include: Livingston Hall,
For early English scholarship describing the rule see: S
Geoffrey P. Miller,
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 156–57 (Austl.); Brown v. Tasmania (2017) 261 CLR 328, 497 (Austl.).
Exceptional uses of the “lenity” label in Australia include six judicial decisions, two transcripts of oral argument in the High Court, and one book chapter: Alcan (NT) Alumina Pty Ltd v. Commissioner of Territory Revenue (Northern Territory) (2009) 239 CLR 27, 49 (Austl.); City of Swan v. Gurney (2011) 186 LGERA 19, 30 (Austl.); Walker Corporation Pty Limited v. Director-General Department of Environment, Climate Change and Water (2012) 82 NSWLR 12, 21 (Austl.); Tabcorp Holdings Limited & Tatts Group Limited v. The Treasurer of Victoria [2013] VSC 324, [27] (Austl.) n.16 (referring to
Gore v. United States, 357 U.S. 386, 391 (1958) (Frankfurter, J.). Earlier uses of the term “lenity” to similar effect can be seen in Ex parte Davis, (No. 3,613) 7 F. Cas. 45, 49 (1851) (quoting from scholarly work: “it was ... one of the laws of the twelve tables of Rome that whenever there was a question between liberty and slavery, the presumption should be on the side of liberty. This excellent principle our law has adopted, in the construction of penal statutes; for whenever any ambiguity arises in a statute, introducing a new penalty or punishment, the decision shall be on the side of lenity and mercy”); Bell v. United States, 349 U.S. 81, 83 (1955) (Frankfurter, J.) (“When Congress leaves to the Judiciary the task of imputing to Congress an undeclared will, the ambiguity should be resolved in favor of lenity. . . . It may fairly be said to be a presupposition of our law to resolve doubts in the enforcement of a penal code against the imposition of a harsher punishment.”); United States v. Turley, 352 U.S. 407, 418 (1957) (Frankfurter, J.) (referring to “the principle of lenity”).
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 95 (1820).
Hall,
Sedima v. Imrex Co., Inc., 473 U.S. 479, 491 n.10 (1985). See also the equation of the two concepts in United States v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259, 266 (1997).
Contrast a Senate Report proposing a statue to eliminate the doctrine of strict construction, which claimed to leave intact the rule of lenity.
For an illustration of this uncertainty see the exchange in oral argument between David Jackson QC and Justice Crennan in Commissioner of Territory Revenue v. Alcan (NT) Alumina Pty Ltd [2009] HCATrans 150 (23 June 2009) (Austl.). Then see the decision, which deliberately skirts the issue: Alcan (NT) Alumina Pty Ltd v. Commissioner of Territory Revenue (Northern Territory) (2009) 239 CLR 27, 49 (Austl.).
Beckwith v. The Queen (1976) 135 CLR 569, 576 (Austl.).
R v. Adams (1935) 53 CLR 563, 567–68 (Austl.).
Murphy v. Farmer (1988) 165 CLR 19, 28–29 (Austl.).
Minister for Immigration & Multicultural Affairs v. Dhingra (2000) 98 FCR 1, 25. See, generally, D. C. P
P
McNally v. United States, 483 U.S. 350, 359–60 (1986);
Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837, 844 (1984) (holding that, when a statute is “silent or ambiguous”, and an administrative agency has resolved that silence in a “reasonable” way, courts should defer to the agency's interpretation of the statute).
The Supreme Court has not definitively resolved the question of whether Chevron applies to criminal statutes.
For a survey of interpretative approaches requiring “ambiguity” as a trigger to their application see Brett Kavanaugh,
Chandler and Co v. Collector of Customs (1907) 4 CLR 1719, 1734 (Austl.) (quoting Nicholson v. Fields (1862) 31 L.J. Ex. 233, 235 (UK)).
R v. A2 [2019] HCA 35, [52] (Austl.).
A
Chapman v. United States, 500 U.S. 453, 463 (1991) (quoting Huddleston v. United States, 415 U.S. 814, 831 (1974)).
Johnson v. United States, 529 U.S. 694, 713 n.13 (2000) (Souter, J.);
This analysis, like the analysis of the United States’ rule, begins with the formation of the federal system. This article therefore does nothing to ameliorate the dearth of scholarship on pre-Federation statutory interpretation in the Australian colonies.
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132 (Austl.).
For scholars citing Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132 (Austl.) as an early authoritative statement of the rule see P
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 142 (Barton, J.) (Austl.).
Chander and Co. v. Collector of Customs (1907) 4 CLR 1719, 1734–35 (Austl.).
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 141 (Griffiths, C.J.) (Austl.). It is interesting to contrast this utterance with his Honour's remarks just a few years earlier in Master Retailers’ Association of New South Wales v. Shop Assistants Union of New South Wales (1904) 2 CLR 94, 106 (Austl.) (“the old distinction between remedial and penal Acts has of late years been much discredited. What has been laid down in modern cases is that the duty of the Court is to interpret Acts according to the intent of the Parliament which passed them.”)
1 W
Reid v. Wilson (1895) 1 WB 315, 320, 322 (UK); Dyke v. Elliot; The Gauntlet (1872) LR 4 PC 184, 191 (UK); Dickenson v. Fletcher (1873) LR 9 CP 1, 7 (UK) all quoted in Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 144–45 (Barton, J.) (Austl.).
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 144–45 (Barton, J.) (Austl.).
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 155–56 (Isaacs, J.) (Austl.) (referring to Caledonian Railway Co v. North British Railway Co (1881) 6 App. Cas. 114, 122 (UK)). It important to note the error of Justice Isaacs’ reference to
Johnson v. Southern Pacific Co 196 U.S. 1, 17, 18 (1904); United States v. Lacher 134 U.S. 624 (1890); United States v. Winn 3 Sumn. 209 (1838) all quoted in Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 156–57 (Isaacs, J.) (Austl.).
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 145 (Barton, J.) (Austl.) (quoting Dyke v. Elliott; The Gauntlet (1872) LR 4 PC 184, 191 (UK)). See also Prior v. Sherwood (1906) 3 CLR 1054, 1072 (Austl.) (quoting Powell v. Kempton Park Racecourse Co. (1897) 2 QB 242, 298 (UK)) (“the Court in construing such a Statute must see that the thing charged is an offence within the plain meaning of the words used, so as to carry out the true intention of the legislature.”)
Scott v. Cawsey (1907) 5 CLR 132, 145 (Barton, J.) (Austl.) (quoting Dickenson v. Fletcher (1873) LR 9 CP 1, 7 (UK)).
Lyons v. Smart (No 1) (1908) 6 CLR 143, 158 (Barton, J.) (Austl.) (emphasis added).
Chandler and Co v. Collector of Customs (1907) 4 CLR 1719, 1734 (O’Connor, J.) (Austl.) (quoting Nicholson v Fields (1862) 31 L.J. Ex. 233, 235 (UK)).
Chandler and Co v. Collector of Customs (1907) 4 CLR 1719, 1735 (O’Connor, J.) (Austl.).
P
Beckwith v. The Queen (1976) 135 CLR 569 (Austl.).
Gans,
Beckwith v. The Queen (1976) 135 CLR 569, 576 (Austl.) (citations omitted).
Waugh v. Kippen (1986) 160 CLR 156, 164 (Austl.).
Beckwith v. The Queen (1976) 135 CLR 569, 576 (Austl.).
United States v. Lacher, 134 U.S. 624, 628 (1890).
Lyons v. Smart (No 1) (1908) 6 CLR 143, 158 (Austl.).
Legislation Act, 2001 (A.C.T.); Interpretation Act, 1987 (N.S.W.); Interpretation Act, 1987 (N.T.); Acts Interpretation Act, 1954 (Qld.); Acts Interpretation Act, 1931 (Tas.); Interpretation of Legislation Act, 1984 (Vic.); Interpretation Act, 1984 (W. Austl.).
P
P
An earlier version read: “In the interpretation of a provision of an Act, a construction that would promote the purpose or object underlying the Act (whether that purpose or object is expressly stated in the Act or not) shall be preferred to a construction that would not promote that purpose or object.” The change to the current wording occurred in 2011 and was effected by the Acts Interpretation Amendment Act, 2011 (Austl.), sched 1. Note the change from “a construction that would promote the purpose” to “the interpretation that would best achieve the purpose”. The new wording is thought to be more prescriptive because, in the event “of a choice between two or more interpretations each of which would promote the Act's purpose or object, … the interpretation that would best achieve that purpose or object must be chosen.”
Acts Interpretation Act § 14 1954 (Qld.).
Acts Interpretation Act § 22 1915 (S. Austl.).
For a discussion of these provisions and their operation see Gans,
Beckwith v. The Queen (1976) 135 CLR 569, 576 (Austl.) (citations omitted).
Brown v. Tasmania (2017) 261 CLR 328, 497 (Austl.).
This analysis, like the analysis of the Australian rule, begins with the establishment of the federal judiciary. There is very little scholarship on the rule's existence (or non-existence) in the case law of the American colonies and then the States prior to 1788.
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 95 (1820);
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 94 (1820).
United States v. R.L.C., 503 U.S. 291, 305 (1992).
United States v. Kozminski, 487 U.S. 931, 952 (1988).
Dunn v. United States, 442 U.S. 100, 112 (1979).
United States v. Rodgers, 466 U.S. 475, 484 (1984).
Whalen v. United States, 445 U.S. 684, 703 (1980) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting).
Adamo Wrecking Co v. United States, 434 U.S. 275, 275 (1978).
United States v. R.L.C., 503 U.S. 291, 310 (1992) (Scalia, J., concurring) (citation omitted).
United States v. Santos, 553 U.S. 507, 515 (2008) (referring to United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76 (1820) as “our seminal rule-of-lenity decision”).
Solan,
Church of the Holy Trinity v. United States, 143 U.S. 457 (1892).
Zachary Price,
Moskal v. United States, 498 U.S. 103, 108 (1990) (quoting Bifulco v. United States, 447 U.S. 381, 387 (1980)) (emphasis added).
United States v. Rodriquez, 553 U.S. 377, 404 (2007) (Souter, J., dissenting) (describing the rule as “a ready tiebreaker . . . which applies where [as here] we have seiz[ed] everything from which aid can be derived, but are left with an ambiguous statute” internal quotation marks omitted, citation omitted); United States v. Canal Barge Co., 631 F.3d 347, 353 (6th Cir. 2011) (“the rule of lenity is only a tiebreaker of last resort”); Markell,
As stated in the text, it is now conventional wisdom in the Supreme Court that lenity ranks after other interpretative methods, as a sort of “tiebreaker”.
A more in depth discussion of the potential constitutional foundations for the American rule can be found in Julian R. Murphy,
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 95 (1820).
United States v. Hudson & Goodwin, 111 U.S. (7 Cranch) 32 (1812).
United States v. Wiltberger, 18 U.S. (5 Wheat.) 76, 94 (1820).
Kahan,
Kahan,
United States v. Bass, 404 U.S. 336, 348 (1971).
Markell,
For early invocations of a Due Process type justification for the rule see United States v. Wilson, 28 F. Cas. 699, 709 (C.C.E.D. Pa. 1830) (No. 16,730) (opinion of Baldwin, J.) (“[The rule] is founded on the tenderness of the law for the rights of individual . . . .”); United States v. Mann, 26 F. Cas. 1153, 1157 (C.C.D.N.H. 1812) (No. 15,718) (opinion of Story, J.); The Enterprise, 8 F. Cas. 732, 734 (C.C.D.N.Y. 1810) (No. 4499) (opinion of Livingston, J.) (“It should be a principle of every criminal code, and certainly belongs to ours, that no person be adjudged guilty of an offence unless it be created and promulgated in terms which leave no reasonable doubt of their meaning.”)
McBoyle v. United States, 283 U.S. 25 (1931).
41 Stat 324 (1919).
41 Stat 324 (1919) § 2(a).
McBoyle v. United States, 283 U.S. 25, 27 (1931).
Dunn v. United States, 442 U.S. 100, 112 (1979).
United States v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259, 266 (1997).
Kahan,
See the survey of Rehnquist-court era cases in Note,
Exceptions include John J. O’Connor,
There is some variance in the literature as to whether the methods of statutory interpretation that take account of federalism ought to be described as one canon or a set of canons. Compare S
Fla. Stat. §775.021 (West 2000) (“The provisions of this code and offenses defined by other statutes shall be strictly construed; when the language is susceptible of differing constructions, it shall be construed most favorably to the accused.”); Ohio Rev. Code Ann. § 2901.04(a) (Anderson 2002) (“sections of the Revised Code defining offenses or penalties shall be strictly construed against the state, and liberally construed in favor of the accused.”)
Ark. Rev. Stat. (1837) c. 129, §§ 22–23 (approved March 5, 1838).
Hall,
Price,
Love,
Modern Penal Code, § 1.02(3). The drafters of the Model Penal Code decided to displace “[t]he ancient rule that penal law must be strictly construed, . . . because it unduly emphasized only one aspect of the problem”.
Pub L No 91-452, § 904(a), 84 Stat 947 (1970) (emphasis added).
David Kurzweil, Note,
United States v. McClendon, 712 F. Supp. 723, 729 (E.D. Ark. 1988).
United States v. Turkette, 452 U.S. 576, 587 (1981).
Sedima, S.P.R.L. v. Imrex Company, Inc., 473 U.S. 479, 491 n.10 (1985); Reves v. Ernst & Young, 507 U.S. 170, 184 n.8 (1993).
Barry Tarlow,
Price,
Jeffries,
Kavanaugh,
Note,
Eskridge,
Nicholas S. Zeppos,
Yates v. United States, 135 S. Ct. 1074 (2015).
It should be noted, however, that the lack of an explicit due process clause in the Australian constitution has not precluded the Courts from protecting certain due process rights.
Shipra Chordia & Andrew Lynch,
Davies,
Elhauge,
Although one could argue that due process and separation of powers principles might afford more law-making latitude to state courts than federal courts given that state courts are charged with the development of common law crimes whereas federal courts are precluded from doing so (United States v. Hudson & Goodwin, 111 U.S. (7 Cranch) 32 (1812)).
Queensland and South Australia, see Acts Interpretation Act § 14 1954 (Qld.); Acts Interpretation Act § 22 1915 (S. Austl.).
Price,
Abbe R. Gluck,
The American rule of lenity has also been described as “a canon of last resort”.