Accesso libero

More than Fitness. A Robustness-based Proposal of a Logical Space to Classify Processes Behind Evolutionary Phenomena

INFORMAZIONI SU QUESTO ARTICOLO

Cita

Alberch, P. (1991). From genes to phenotypes: dynamical systems and evolvability. Genetica 84, 5–11.10.1007/BF00123979Search in Google Scholar

Birch, J. (2014), “Has Grafen formalized Darwin?”, Biol Philos, 29: 175–180.10.1007/s10539-013-9421-zSearch in Google Scholar

Callebaut, W., Rasskin-Gutman, eds. (2005). Modularity. Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems. The MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/4734.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Carlson, J.M., Doyle, J. (2002). Complexity and Robustness. PNSA, vol. 99, 2538–2545.10.1073/pnas.012582499Search in Google Scholar

Charnov, E.L. (1976). Optimal Foraging, the Marginal Value Theorem, Theoretical Population Biology, Vol. 9, No. 2.10.1016/0040-5809(76)90040-XSearch in Google Scholar

Daniels, B.C. et al. (2008), Sloppiness, robustness and evolvability in systems biology, Current Opinion in Biotecnology, 19: 389–395.10.1016/j.copbio.2008.06.008Search in Google Scholar

Dennet, D.C. (1995). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, Penguin Books.Search in Google Scholar

Draghi, J.A. et al. (2010). Mutational robustness can facilitate adaptation, Nature, 463: 353–355.10.1038/nature08694Search in Google Scholar

Eldredge, N. & Gould, S.J. (1972), Punctuated equilibria: an alternative to phyletic gradualism, in Models in paleobiology, Shopf, TJM Freeman, Cooper / Co.10.5531/sd.paleo.7Search in Google Scholar

Fisher, R.A. (1930). Genetical theory of natural selection. S.l.: Oxford Clarendon Press.10.5962/bhl.title.27468Search in Google Scholar

Gould S.J., Lewontin S.J. (1979), The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist program, Proc. R. Soc. Lon., B 205, 581–598.10.1098/rspb.1979.0086Search in Google Scholar

Gould, J.S., Vrba, E.S. (1982), Exaptation – A Missing Term in the Science of Form, Paleobiology, Vol. 8, No. 1: 4–15.10.1017/S0094837300004310Search in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (1999) “Formal Darwinism, the individual-as-maximizing-agent and bet-edging”, Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B., 266, 799–803.10.1098/rspb.1999.0708Search in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (2000) “Development of the Price equation and natural selection under uncertainty” Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B., 267, 1223–1227.10.1098/rspb.2000.1131Search in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (2002) “A first formal link between the Price equation and an optimization program”, J. Theor. Biol. 217, 75–91.10.1006/jtbi.2002.3015Search in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (2007) “The Formal Darwinism project: a mid-term report”, J. Evol. Biol., 1243–1254.10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01321.xSearch in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (2014a) “The formal Darwinism project in outline”, Biol Philos, 29: 155–174.10.1007/s10539-013-9414-ySearch in Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (2014b) “The formal Darwinism project in outline: response to commentaries”, Biol Philos, 29: 281–29210.1007/s10539-013-9413-zSearch in Google Scholar

Haldane, J.B. (1932). The Causes of Evolution. Longmans Green.Search in Google Scholar

Hall, B.K. (2003a). Evo-Devo: evolutionary developmental mechanisms. Int. J. Dev. Biol. 47: 491–495.Search in Google Scholar

Hall, B.K. (2003b). Unlocking the Black Box between Genotype and Phenotype: Cells and Cell Condensations as Morphogenetic (modular) Units. Biol. & Philos., 18: 219–247.10.1023/A:1023984018531Search in Google Scholar

Kauffman, S., (2000). Investigations. Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Kimura, M. (1983). The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511623486Search in Google Scholar

Kitano, H. (2004). Biological robustness. Nature Reviews Genetics, 5(11), 826–837. doi:10.1038/nrg1471.10.1038/nrg1471Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Kitano, H (2007). Towards a theory of biological robustness. Molecular Systems Biology, 3(1), 137-n/a. doi:10.1038/msb4100179.10.1038/msb4100179Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Lenski, R.E., Barrick, J.E., & Ofria, C. (2006). Balancing robustness and evolvability. PLoS Biology, 4(12), e428. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.004042810.1371/journal.pbio.0040428Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Masel, J., & Siegal, M.L. (2009). Robustness: Mechanisms and consequences. Trends in Genetics, 25(9), 395–403. doi:10.1016/j.tig.2009.07.005.10.1016/j.tig.2009.07.005Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Maturana, H., & Varela, F.J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.10.1007/978-94-009-8947-4Search in Google Scholar

Haldane, J.B. (1932). The Causes of Evolution. Longmans Green.Search in Google Scholar

McShea, D., Brandon, R. (2010). Biology’s First Law: the tendency for diversity and complexity to increase in evolutionary systems. The University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226562278.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Mills, S., Beatty, J. (1979), The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness, Philosophy of Science, 46: 263–286.10.1086/288865Search in Google Scholar

Millstein, R.L. (2006). Natural selection as a population-level causal process. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(4):627–653.10.1093/bjps/axl025Search in Google Scholar

Mocczek, A.P. (2008). On the origins of novelty in development and evolution. BioEssays 30: 432–477.10.1002/bies.20754Search in Google Scholar

Neander, K. (1995). Pruning the Tree of Life. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(1): 59–80.10.1093/bjps/46.1.59Search in Google Scholar

Orzack, S.H. & Sober, E.R., eds. (2001). Adaptationism and Optimality. Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511609084Search in Google Scholar

Parker, G., Maynard Smith, J. (1990). Optimality theory in evolutionary biology, Nature, 348: 27–33.10.1038/348027a0Search in Google Scholar

Pigliucci, M. (2008). Is evolvability evolvable? Nature Reviews Genetics, 9(1), 75–82. doi:10.1038/nrg2278.10.1038/nrg2278Open DOISearch in Google Scholar

Popper, K. (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge.Search in Google Scholar

Price, G.R. (1972). Fisher’s ‘fundamental theorem’ made clear. Annals of Human Genetics, 36(2), 129.10.1111/j.1469-1809.1972.tb00764.xSearch in Google Scholar

Prum, R.O. (1999). Development and evolutionary origin of feathers. J. Exp. Zool. B Moi. Dev. Evol. 285: 391–306.10.1002/(SICI)1097-010X(19991215)285:4<291::AID-JEZ1>3.0.CO;2-9Search in Google Scholar

Rice SH (2004) Evolutionary Theory: Mathematical and Conceptual Foundations. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, MA.Search in Google Scholar

Rosenberg, A. (1982). On the Propensity Definition of Fitness. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 49, No. 2:268–273.10.1086/289056Search in Google Scholar

Rosenberg, A., Williams, M. (1986). Fitness as Primitive and Propensity. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 53, No. 3:412–418.10.1086/289326Search in Google Scholar

Sober, E. (1998) Six Sayings about Adaptationism in D. Hull and M. Ruse (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. Oxford University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Sober, E (2009). Philosophy of biology. New York: Westview Press.Search in Google Scholar

Van’t Hoff et al. (2016). The industrial melanism mutation in British peppered moths is a transposable element. Nature 534: 102–105.10.1038/nature17951Search in Google Scholar

Waddington, C.H. (1957). The Strategy of the Genes. George Allen & Unwin.Search in Google Scholar

Wagner, A., (2007). Robustness and Evolvability in Living Systems, Princeton University Press.Search in Google Scholar

Wagner, A., (2011), The Origins of Evolutionary Innovations, Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199692590.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Wagner, A., (2015). Arrival of the Fittest, Oneworld Publications.Search in Google Scholar

Wright, S. (1982), The shifting balance theory and macroevolution, Ann. Rev. Genet. 16:1–19.10.1146/annurev.ge.16.120182.000245Search in Google Scholar

eISSN:
1647-659X
Lingua:
Inglese
Frequenza di pubblicazione:
3 volte all'anno
Argomenti della rivista:
Philosophy, Metaphysics, Ontology, Epistemology, Philosophy of Science