[Bermúdez, J.L. (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195159691.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Block, N. (1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19–49.10.2307/1522889]Search in Google Scholar
[Brooks, R. (1995). Intelligence Without Reason. In L. Steels & R. Brooks (Eds.), The Artificial Life Route to Artificial Intelligence: Building Embodied, Situated Agents. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.]Search in Google Scholar
[Brooks, R., & Stein, L.A. (1993). Building Brains for Bodies (1439). Retrieved from http://people.csail.mit.edu/brooks/papers/brains.pdf]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A., & Toribio, A.J. (1994). Doing without representing. Synthese, 10, 401-431.10.1007/BF01063896]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195333213.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2012a). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind 121 (483), 753-771. doi: 10.1093/mind/fzs106.10.1093/mind/fzs106]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2012b). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 36(3), 181–253.10.1017/S0140525X12000477]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2015a). Embodied prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds). Open MIND (7), 1-21. doi: 10.15502/9783958570115.]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2015b). Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190217013.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs 00:0, 1-27. doi:10.1111/nous.12140.10.1111/nous.12140]Search in Google Scholar
[Clowes, R.W. (2017). The Ipseity Disturbance Theory of Schizophrenia and Predictive Processing. In I. Hipólito, J. Gonçalves, & J. G. Pereira (Eds.), Schizophrenia and Common Sense: explaining madness and social values. : Springer Mind Brain Studies.]Search in Google Scholar
[Clowes, R.W., & Chrisley, R. (2012). Virtualist Representation. International Journal of Machine Consciousness, 04(02), 503-522.10.1142/S179384301240029X]Search in Google Scholar
[Clowes, R.W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation Redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, Special Issue on Representation(Special Issue: Explaining Representation), 26-47.10.1016/j.newideapsych.2015.03.002]Search in Google Scholar
[Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation-hunger reconsidered. Synthese, 191 (15), 3639-3648.10.1007/s11229-014-0484-4]Search in Google Scholar
[Di Paolo, E. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9-21.10.1007/s11245-008-9042-3]Search in Google Scholar
[Di Paolo, E., & Thompson, E. (2014). The enactive approach. The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition, 68-78.]Search in Google Scholar
[Fletcher, P. & Frith, C. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews: Neuro-science 10, 48–58.10.1038/nrn2536]Search in Google Scholar
[Fodor, J. (1981). Representations, Cambridge: MIT Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Fresco, N. (2010). Explaining Computation Without Semantics: Keeping it Simple. Minds and Machines 20(2), 165–181. doi:10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6.10.1007/s11023-010-9199-6]Search in Google Scholar
[Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 293-301.10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005]Search in Google Scholar
[Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0199271941.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Gładziejewski, P. (2015). Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese 193, 559–582 doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9.10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9]Search in Google Scholar
[Haugeland, J. (1990). The intentionality all-stars. Philosophical perspectives, 383-427.10.2307/2214199]Search in Google Scholar
[Hohwy, J. (2004). Top-down and bottom-up in delusion formation. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11(1), 65-70.10.1353/ppp.2004.0043]Search in Google Scholar
[Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682737.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Hohwy, J. (2014). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12062.10.1111/nous.12062]Search in Google Scholar
[Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A. & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition 108(3), 687–701.10.1016/j.cognition.2008.05.010]Search in Google Scholar
[Hume, D. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature (Second Edition). Sir Lewis Amherst Selby-Bigge, first baronet & P. H. Nidditch (eds.). Oxford University Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D. (2011). Enactivism: Why be radical. Sehen und Handeln, 21-44.]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D. (2015). REC: Revolution Effected by Clarification. Topoi, 1-15. doi:10.1007/s11245-015-9358-8.10.1007/s11245-015-9358-8]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D., Kirchhoff, M. D., & Abrahamson, D. (2015). The enactive roots of STEM: rethinking educational design in mathematics. Educational Psychology Review, 27(3), 371-389.10.1007/s10648-015-9326-2]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D., & Myin, E. (Forthcoming). Going Radical. Retrieved from https://www.academia.edu/15763822/Going_Radical?auto=download.]Search in Google Scholar
[Hutto, D.D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521-536.10.1007/s11406-015-9644-0]Search in Google Scholar
[Kriegel, U. (2002). PANIC Theory and the Prospects for a Representationalist Theory of Phenomenal Consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 15, 55-64.10.1080/09515080120109414]Search in Google Scholar
[Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9781139171434.009]Search in Google Scholar
[Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (1999). Concepts: core readings: Mit Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Miłkowski M. (2013). A mechanistic account of computational explanation in cognitive science. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Cooperative Minds: Social Interaction and Group Dynamics, Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society, 3050–3055. Available online at: http://csjarchive.cogsci.rpi.edu/Proceedings/2013/papers/0545/paper0545.pdf.]Search in Google Scholar
[Miłkowski, M. (2016a). Function and causal relevance of content. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 94-102.10.1016/j.newideapsych.2014.12.003]Search in Google Scholar
[Miłkowski, M. (2016b). Unification Strategies in Cognitive Science. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 48(61), 13-33.10.1515/slgr-2016-0053]Search in Google Scholar
[O’Regan, J.K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939-973.10.1017/S0140525X01000115]Search in Google Scholar
[Piccinini, G. (2006). Computation without Representation. Philosophical Studies 137(2), 205–241. doi:10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4.10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4]Search in Google Scholar
[Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical Computation: A Mechanistic Account. Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199658855.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Pitt, D. (2013). Mental Representation. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2013 Edition, URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/mental-representation/>.]Search in Google Scholar
[Sacks, O. (2012). Hallucinations: Pan Macmillan.]Search in Google Scholar
[Seth, A.K., Suzuki, K. & Critchley, H.D. (2011). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology 2, 395.]Search in Google Scholar
[Shoemaker, S. (1994): Identity, Cause, and Mind. Cambridge University Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Steels, L. (1997). Constructing and Sharing Perceptual Distinctions. Paper presented at the Proceedings of the European Conference on Machine Learning, Prague. Springer Verlag, Berlin.10.1007/3-540-62858-4_68]Search in Google Scholar
[Steels, L., & Belpaeme, T. (2005). Coordinating Perceptually Grounded Categories through Language: A Case Study for Colour. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 469-489.10.1017/S0140525X05000087]Search in Google Scholar
[Stich, S. (1983). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. The MIT Press.]Search in Google Scholar
[Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton University Press.10.1515/9780691186672]Search in Google Scholar
[Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6730.001.0001]Search in Google Scholar
[Watson, J.B. (1913). Psychology as the Behaviorist Views it. Psychological Review 20, 158-177.10.1037/h0074428]Search in Google Scholar